Archive for April, 2017

The Basics of Ćwarmin Folk Dances

Sunday, April 30th, 2017
The Ćwarmin tribes are increasingly adopting sedentism, but many tribes still retain very nomadic lifestyles. Many of the traditions and rituals among the sedentist tribes stem from nomadic rituals, and many of the dances have ritual use.

A very common type of dance happens before setting up a new camp, or building additional tents or structures (and in the sedentist tribes, before building a new house). One style of dance consists of placing sticks in geometric patterns on the ground: crosses, "asterisks", and sometimes tiled patterns are made. Dancers place themselves in symmetric or pseudosymmetric patterns, and make sequences of steps over and back across the sticks, often in various symmetric patterns, although with certain layouts, the ends of the shape may require some different step sequence. Oftentimes, these step sequences are the length of two regular step sequences.

Dances in large crosses or asterisks often move in and out along the diameter - often they have a "chorus" part, where the dancers close to the middle grip each others hands (in a variety of ways, depending on the dance) and do some slightly different moves from in the "verse", and now often in some quite simple fashion around the centre.

Sometimes, the final chorus part also differs from the earlier choruses. In some dances, the sticks are moved somewhat in the middle (often really a bit into the second half, length-wise). This is often carried out as a special version of the second main genre of stick dance, where the dancers hit each others' sticks generating percussive sounds as they do so. These often also contain parts where the sticks are hit together in various ways that often feature a significant amount of syncopation.
 
The final part of such a three-part dance often has the same music as the first part, but with a new arrangement of steps and sticks.

At weddings, married couples often dance either opposite each other or next to each other, unmarried dancers do not dance next to or opposite anyone, and the couple who are building their first common tent move, during the dance, from not being opposite/next to one another to being so. Depending on the region, this may require short movements (just getting one step ahead) or large movements (moving slowly around a large segment of the figure). In other dances, the married couple will dance a 'duet' in an exceptional spot - in the middle of a large figure - and often in an exceptional pattern.

Typologies:

Groupings and symmetries: oftentimes, everyone moves in the same pattern. Such dances are fully symmetrical. Some may permit for gaps. Sometimes, men and women dance in different patterns. Sometimes, one of the genders are divided into two groups with different patterns each. It is unusual, but not unattested for a dance to have two separate groups per gender. Finally, some dances are only for one gender – and such dances also sometimes divide the dancers into as many as three groups.

These are single, double and triple dances (depending on the number of groups), and they usually have rotational or transpositional symmetry.

Finally, four kinds of dances exist where one must consider there to be several 'bunches' of people that move together, rather than separate people moving in similar patterns. In three of these, the bunches all behave similarly, in the final one, the behavior of the groups starts out similarly, until one group breaks the ranks, and after awhile another group also breaks the ranks, and ends up converging on the first group to break ranks. Finally, the whole set converges.

Stick setups: polygons, combs ( |_|_|_|_| ), often symmetrical across the spine ( -|-|-|- ), squares-with-combs (#, possibly with more arms) stars (pentagrams,  hexagrams, larger ones are uncommon), crosses and asterisks (+, *, with odd or even numbers of arms permitted). For the second style of dance, there's two main setups: short sticks in each hand, or long stick held by both. Sometimes, different dancers may have different setups in such dances.

Stick transitions: Most dances that include stick transitions go between a comb or square-with-comb layout and a cross or asterisk layout.

Rhythms: Mostly the rhythms consist of short slightly lilting pulses, basically alternating strong and weak, short and long beats. Length and strength combine both ways.





Detail #338: A Voice – Dereflexive

Tuesday, April 25th, 2017
Consider a language where the only pronominal way of distinguishing third persons is the distincyion between reflexive and regular third persons.

In cases where only one third person is prominent, this is not widely used but sometimes the distinction is used outside its origin in reflexivity.

Here, we can consider a situation where a  basic voice marker and the reflexive marker - be they of whatever kind you want - combine forces to form a "dereflexive" - a voice that lacks a proper subject, but instead has a reflexive marking that is the real subject of the thing.

The Interrogatives in Sargaĺk

Monday, April 17th, 2017
In Sargaĺk, there are four interrogative pronouns -
t'əre: who
səre: what (for count-noun-like things)
bəre: what (for mass-noun-like things)
zəre: what (for utterances and thoughts)
These sometimes appear in a variety of verbs, adjectives and nouns.
The interrogative pronouns are inflected for case (and number), but t'əre is most often masculine except if a) the expected answer is feminine, or b) the answer is required by the speaker to be feminine. The three others are always inflected in the masculine except if they are adjectives; as adjectives, they are generally suffixed to the noun.

Adjectives 

Adjectives are generally formed from other stems by adding suffixes. These suffixes further are inflected for case. 
brəsep - full (of liquid or indifferentiable mass)
zrəsep - full of things to say
t'rəsep - full of people
The suffix -sep means 'full of' or 'saturated with'. The -e- turns to -É™- when case suffixes are added.
sərkuy - 'whatless', insignificant
bərkuy - 'empty'
zərkuy - 'silent' but also 'unthinking' depending on context
t'ərkuy - 'one of a kind' (of a person)
The meaning of -kuy generally is '-less'.  -y- disappears before consonant-initial case suffixes.

From these, nominalizations can be formed, but the usual Sargaĺk discourse structure seldom calls for abstract nouns like '-lessness' or '-fulness'. -kir, however, is the usual abstract nominalization for adjectives: brəsefkir: fullness, t'ərkukir: quirkiness, zərkukir: silence, stupidity.

These can be used with appropriate case inflections to signify 'a X one', including the uninflected form for the absolutive case. 'Brəsep' thus can also signify a full container, 'zrəsep' a person with an issue to speak of, or a story-teller, or somesuch, and a t'rəsep can be a full house or a legion or anything like that.

Nouns

There are only a few derivations from these that give nouns without an intermediate adjective or verb in the derivation chain. Three primary examples, however, are
srənki (f) - a question (as to what (səre or bəre))
t'rənki (f) - a question (as to whom)
zrənki (f) - a question (as to what the listener is thinking)

Verbs

Verbs for asking are obvious contenders for this, and include
zrənoj, t'rənoj, brənoj, srənoj
Brənoj and srənoj both are used when the question pertains to time, place, etc, depending on the size and type of the expected answer: spans of time or large locations or maritime locations often are asked for with brənoj, specific days or times of day or weeks or months are asked for with srənoj.
There is also a verb k'yenoj which signifies asking a binary question. K'ye also is the particle that indicates tag questions, and can be initial or final in the tag question.

Other verbs for asking specific types of questions also exist, such as
bnaroj - ask for permission
The idea that asking for whom is somehow the primary type of question can be found in the following verbs, which can refer to any kind of question:
t'rəgrošaj: to overwhelm with questions
t'rəkoŋpoj: to ask questions with the intention of misleading the listener
t'rəroroj: to ask stupid questions
t'rəksturij: to ask a question without an intention to listen to the answer
t'rəksomaj: to ask the same question repeatedly
t'rəparuj: to ask a question in order to embarass someone

Clitics in Ayeri: Thoughts and Notes

Sunday, April 16th, 2017

For the past months, work on writing my grammar has been stalling since I’ve been trying to figure out which of the functional morphemes that are maybe a little untypical as inflections might in fact be clitics. After having read Spencer and Luís (2012) on the topic nearly cover-to-cover, I’ve become a little disenchanted about the whole effort, since clitics appear to be very elusive things which can’t be easily defined in a formal way (126). Based on my reading, some characteristic traits appear to be:1

  • Clitics behave in part like function words and in part like affixes, but in any case they are not free morphemes (38, 42).
  • Clitics tend to be phonologically weak items (39).
  • Clitics prominently—and importantly—tend to attach ‘promiscuously’ to surrounding words. That is, unlike inflection, they are not limited to connect to a certain part of speech or to align with their host in semantics (40, 108–109).
  • Clitics tend to appear in a second position, whether that is after a word or an intonational or syntactic phrase (41)
  • Clitics tend to be templatic and to cluster, especially if they encode inflection-like information (41, 47–48).
  • Clitics have none of the freedom of ordering found in true words and phrases (43).
  • Positions of ‘special’ clitics tend to not be available to free words (44).
  • Clitics tend to be functional morphemes, and to realize a single morphosyntactic property (67, 179).
  • There are no paradigmatic gaps (108–109).
  • There tends to be no morphophonemic alteration like vowel harmony, stress shift or sandhi between a clitic and its host (108–109).
  • There tends to be no idiosyncratic change in meaning when a clitic and a clitic host come together, unlike there may be with inflection (108, 110).
  • Similar to affixes, clitics and their host tend to be treated as a syntactic unit, that is, there is lexical integrity, so you can’t put word material in between a clitic and its host (108, 110).
  • Clitics usually get joined to a host word after inflection (108, 110)
  • Affixes tend to go on every word in a conjunct (narrow scope), while clitics have a tendency to treat a conjunct as a unit to attach to (wide scope; 139, 196 ff.).

However, Spencer and Luís (2012) point out many counterexamples in order to drive their point home that the border between clitics and affixes is often fuzzy. It comes as no surprise that according to their assessment, there’s a lot of miscategorization in individual grammars as a result (107). Another consequence of definitional fuzziness is that since not all of the traits described above are always present, making a checklist and summing up the tally is only of limited value. The traits enumerated above are sufficient, but not necessary, conditions.

This blog article has become rather long and technical in retrospect, but I needed to write it all down in order to get a clear head about the status of various particles and affixes in Ayeri which behave not quite like function words or inflection, and which I’ve thus long suspected to belong to the interstitial category of clitics. The first part of this article will detail all the particles and affixes which precede the lexical heads they modify, the second one will elaborate on suffixes. This article is also likely to find its way into the 2016/17 edition of the Ayeri Grammar, which I’m still working on, as a subchapter to the chapter on morphological typology.

1. Preposed particles and prefixes

Now, I think what should be rather unproblematic with regards to analysis as clitics in Ayeri are the preverbal elements, that is, the topic marker, one or several modal particles, the progressive marker, and also the emphatic affirmative and negative discourse particles. All of these particles essentially have functional rather than lexical content, and are usually unstressed. They come in a cluster with a fixed order, and they appear in a position where no ordinary word material could go, since Ayeri is strictly verb-initial. In conjuncts it’s also unnecessary to mark every verb with one or several of them:

    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      kece
      ket-ye
      wash-3SG.F
      nay
      nay
      and
      dayungisaye
      dayungisa-ye
      dress-3SG.F
      māva
      māva-Ø
      mother-TOP
      yanjas
      yan-ye-as
      boy-PL-P
      yena.
      yena
      3SG.F.GEN

      ‘The mother washes and dresses her boys.’
    2. Manga
      manga
      PROG
      sahaya
      saha-ya
      come-3SG.M
      rangya
      rang-ya
      home-LOC
      nay
      nay
      and
      nedraya
      nedra-ya
      sit-3SGM
      ang
      ang
      A
      Tikim.
      Tikim
      Tikim

      ‘Tikim is coming home and sitting down.’
    3. Ang
      ang
      AT
      mya
      mya
      be.supposed.to
      ming
      ming
      can
      sidegongya
      sideg-ong-ya.Ø
      repair-IRR-3SG.M.TOP
      nay
      nay
      and
      la-lataya
      la~lata-ya.Ø
      ITER~sell-3SG.M.TOP
      ajamyeley.
      ajam-ye-ley
      toy-PL-P.INAN

      ‘He should be able to repair and resell the toys.’

In (1a), therefore, the agent-topic marker ang only occurs before kece ‘(she) washes’, and the conjoined verb dayungisaye ‘(she) dresses’ is also within its scope. Repeating the marker as well before the latter verb could either be considered ungrammatical because there is only one topic there—māva ‘mother’—or the sentence could be interpreted as having two conjoined clauses with different subjects: ‘She1 washes and mother2 dresses her boys.’ The latter outcome has māva as the topic only of dayungisaye, while kece‘s topic is the person marking on the verb—a pro-drop subject, essentially.

In (1b), then, the progressive marker manga equally has scope over both verb conjuncts, sahaya ‘(he) comes’ and nedraya ‘(he) sits’ in what I presume is a case of extended/distributed exponence, since the verb conjuncts can be represented by the incomplete f-structure matrix (cf. Bresnan et al. 2016; Butt and King 2015) shown in (2). Manga is treated there as being part of things the verb inflects for, that is, progressive aspect. The topic marker ang is not a semantic property of the verb, but announces the case and—for agents and patients—the animacy value of the topicalized noun phrases (NPs), so the f-structure in (2) lists this information under the TOP relation.

  1. Part of the f-structure of saha- ‘come’ in (1b):

    PRED ‘come ⟨(↑ SUBJ), (↑ OBLloc)⟩’
    ASP PROG
    TOP
    CASE A
    ANIM +

Modal particles, exemplified in (1c), are probably slightly less typical as clitics since it seems feasible for them to be stressed for contrast. What is not possible, however, is to front either mya or ming, and the verb itself also can’t precede the particles, which is demonstrated in (3). It’s also not possible to coordinate any of the elements in the preverbal particle cluster with nay ‘and’, as we will see in (4).

    1. * mya ang ming sidegongya
    2. * ming ang mya sidegongya
    3. * sidegongya ang mya ming
    1. * ang nay mya ming sidegongya
    2. * ang mya nay ming sidegongya
    3. * ang mya ming nay sidegongya

It needs to be pointed out that unlike verbs, modal particles in Ayeri resist inflection, so in (1c) the irrealis suffix -ong is realized on the verb sidegongya ‘(he) would repair’ instead of on one or both of the modal particles as * mingong and * myong, respectively. The combination of mya ‘be supposed to’ with an irrealis-marked verb together indicates that the speaker thinks the action denoted by the verb should be carried out. On the other hand, the marking on the verb may also be interpreted as being valid for the whole verb complex, and just generally adds the feature [MOOD IRR] to the verb’s feature list in analogy to [ASP PROG] in (2). With regards to negation, it’s just the same: only the verb can be negated, but not the modal particle. Possibly, it would be useful in this case to abstract the modal particles as a feature [MODALITY] as listed by ParGram for purposes of functional representation. At least superficially, it looks as though Ayeri acts differently from English here in that the verb is possibly not a complement of the modal. I suppose that this is mostly apparent from the fact that in Ayeri, the verb inflects, not the modal particle. Furthermore, modal particles in Ayeri can’t be modified by adverbs like regular verbs can:

    1. Ming
      ming
      can
      tigalye
      tigal-ye
      swim-3SG.F
      ban
      ban
      well
      nilay
      nilay
      probably
      ang
      ang
      A
      Diya.
      Diya
      Diya

      ‘Diya can probably swim well.’
    2. * 
      Ming
      ming
      can
      nilay
      nilay
      probably
      tigalye
      tigal-ye
      swim-3SG.F
      ban
      ban
      well
      ang
      ang
      A
      Diya.
      Diya
      Diya

In order to not confuse things even more, it seems advisable to decree that combinations of topic particle and modal particle, as well as modal particle and verb, likewise not be interrupted by parenthetical material like naratang ‘they say’, so that:

    1. * 
      ​​Naratang,​​
      nara-tang
      say-3PL.M.A
      ang
      ang
      AT
      ming
      ming
      can
      tigalye
      tigal-ye
      swim-3SG.F
      ban
      ban
      well
      Diya
      Diya
      Diya
      kodanya.
      kodan-ya
      lake-LOC

      ‘They say Diya can swim well in a lake.’
    2. * Ang, naratang, ming tigalye ban Diya kodanya.
    3. * Ang ming, naratang, tigalye ban Diya kodanya.
    4. ? Ang ming tigalye, naratang, ban Diya kodanya.
    5. Ang ming tigalye ban, naratang, Diya kodanya.
    6. Ang ming tigalye ban Diya, naratang, kodanya.
    7. Ang ming tigalye ban Diya kodanya, naratang.

Of all the other parts of speech, only nouns also have preposed modifiers. This is the case with proper nouns, where the name will be preceded by a case marker instead of receiving a case-marking suffix. This case marker is phonologically weak in that it is no longer than other affixes, and unstressed, with the exception of the causative case marker sā, which bears at least secondary stress since it contains a long vowel. We already saw case particles preceding names in (1b) and (5) above: ang Tikim and ang Diya; ang marks the proper-noun NPs as agents in both cases. The case marker is missing when the NP is topicalized, as exemplified by (6), where the agent NP appears as just Diya, not ang Diya. While case suffixes have narrow scope as in (7a) and thus need to be repeated on every NP in a conjunct, preposed case markers may be used with wide scope if both conjuncts are proper nouns as in (7c). Narrow scope with proper nouns may add an individuating connotation in (7d).

    1. Toryon
      tor-yon
      sleep-3PL.N
      veneyang
      veney-ang
      dog-A
      nay
      nay
      and
      badanang.
      badan-ang
      father-A

      ‘The dog and father are (both) sleeping.’
    2. * 
      Toryon
      tor-yon
      sleep-3PL.N
      veney
      veney_
      dog_
      nay
      nay
      and
      badanang.
      badan-ang
      father-A
    3. Sa
      sa
      PT
      sobisayan
      sobisa-yan
      study-3PL.M
      ang
      ang
      A
      Niva
      Niva
      Niva
      nay
      nay
      and
      Mico
      Mico
      Mico
      narānye.
      narān-ye-Ø
      language-PL-TOP

      ‘Languages is what Niva and Mico study.’
    4. Sa
      sa
      PT
      sobisayan
      sobisa-yan
      study-3PL.M
      ang
      ang
      A
      Niva
      Niva
      Niva
      nay
      nay
      and
      ang
      ang
      A
      Mico
      Mico
      Mico
      narānye.
      narān-ye-Ø
      language-PL-TOP

      ‘Languages is what Niva and Mico (each) study.’

Taking the above characteristics into account, one may argue that the preposed case markers are clitics. They also often enough follow other phonetic material, so it should be possible to analyze case markers as indiscriminately attaching to the word on the left while syntactically modifying the word to the right:

  1. ? Sa sobisayan=ang Niva nay Mico narānye.

There is no audible break or change in intonation between sobisayan and ang, and there is also no morphophonemic modification occurring between them either: if ang were a suffix, stress would shift from /sobiˈsajan/ to /sobiËŒsajaˈnang/. According to Klavans (1985), a clitic’s phonological leaning to the preceding word while modifying the following one is a process which is attested in natural languages, and she quotes examples from Kwak’wala, a Wakashan language of British Columbia (Hammarström et al. 2017), for instance:

  1. Adapted from Klavans (1985: 106):
      [Kwak’wala]
    1. nəp’idi-da
      throw-DEIC
      gənanəm
      child
      [x̣a
      OBJ
      gukʷ]​​​N​​​
      house
      [sa
      OBL
      t’isəm]​​​N​​​
      rock

      ‘The child hit the house with a rock by throwing.’ (Levine 1980)

Since clitics should be treated as syntactically coherent with their hosts, it shouldn’t be possible, then, to interrupt sobisayan and ang with parenthetical word material in the same way it wasn’t possible in (6). This assumption proves false, however, since Ayeri does not take an issue with placing things other than a case marker after the verb cluster and before the first NP, while the interruption of ang and Niva, on the other hand, is indeed ungrammatical:

    1. Sa
      sa
      PT
      sobisayan,
      sobisa-yan
      study-3PL.M
      naratang,
      nara-tang
      say-3PL.M.A
      ang
      ang
      A
      Niva
      Niva
      Niva
      nay
      nay
      and
      Mico
      Mico
      Mico
      narānye.
      narān-ye-Ø
      language-PL-TOP

      ‘Languages is what Niva and Mico, they say, study.’
    2. * 
      Sa
      sa
      PT
      sobisayan
      sobisa-yan
      study-3PL.M
      ang,
      ang
      A
      naratang,
      nara-tang
      say-3PL.M.A
      Niva
      Niva
      Niva
      nay
      nay
      and
      Mico
      Mico
      Mico
      narānye.
      narān-ye-Ø
      language-PL-TOP

It is furthermore possible for the case marker to begin an utterance, namely, in equative sentences like the one in (11a). In this case, there is no way for the case marker to lean on a host to its left, but only to its right. In these cases as well, it isn’t possible for parenthetical material to be placed between the case marker and its target of modification, as in (11b).

    1. Ang
      ang
      A
      Misan
      Misan
      Misan
      lajāyas
      lajāy-as
      student-P
      puti.
      puti
      zealous

      ‘Misan is a zealous student.’
    2. * 
      Ang,
      ang
      A
      paronyang,
      paron-yang
      believe-1SG.A
      Misan
      Misan
      Misan
      lajāyas
      lajāy-as
      student-P
      puti.
      puti
      zealous

Since the case marker and its modification target cohere that closely, we have to assume that here as well, the case marker is proclitic rather than enclitic. Unlike “typical” clitics, however, its attachment is not strictly speaking ‘promiscuous’, unlike in our first hypothesis, but always with a proper noun very specifically. This property puts it very close to an affix—just like the suffixed case markers. More typical of function words, though, there is no morphophonemic interaction between the flexive and the word it inflects, for example, there is no /saːdÊ’aːn/ from sa (P) + Ajān. This overlap in form between affix and function word is typical of clitics, according to the traits excerpted from Spencer and Luís (2012) above, and what Klavans (1985) characterizes as “double citizenship”. Moreover, sā, as mentioned above, represents an exception to other case particles in that it takes secondary stress due to being a long syllable, which cannot be unstressed. Ayeri does not allow words to end in secondary-stressed syllables, but only allows secondary-stressed syllables to precede a stressed one, since word stress spreads backwards from the right edge of phonological words. If we don’t want to create an exception for sā alone, thus, it is more likely for the preposed case markers to lean to the right rather than to the left also on phonological grounds, like in (12).

  1. Sa sobisayan ang=Niva nay Mico narānye.

From this discussion of prenominal particles, let us return to verbs again for a moment. Besides the preverbal particles discussed above, there is also what is spelled as a prefix on the verb which appears to be a little odd as such in that it can have wide scope over conjoined verbs. This is the prefix da- often meaning ‘so, thus’, displayed in (13).

  1. Ang
    ang
    AT
    da-pinyaya
    da-pinya-ya
    so-ask-3SG.M
    nay
    nay
    and
    hisaya
    hisa-ya
    beg-3SG.M
     
    Ø
    TOP
    Yan
    Yan
    Yan
    sa
    sa
    P
    Pila.
    Pila
    Pila

    ‘Yan asks and begs Pila to (do so).’

Da-, where it is not used for presentative purposes,2 is a functional morpheme in that it basically acts as an anaphora for a complementizer phrase (CP) the speaker chooses to drop. Thus, it does not mark any of the intrinsic morphological categories of the verb (tense, aspect, mood, modality, finiteness), just like the topic marker refers to a syntactic relation the verb subcategorizes but none of its inflectional categories. As an anaphora, da- cannot stand alone, though it is possible to use a full demonstrative form danya ‘such one’ in its place:

  1. Ang
    ang
    AT
    da-pinyaya
    da-pinya-ya
    so-ask-3SG.M
    nay
    nay
    and
    hisaya
    hisa-ya
    beg-3SG.M
     
    Ø
    TOP
    Yan
    Yan
    Yan
    sa
    sa
    P
    Pila
    Pila
    Pila
    danyaley.
    danya-ley
    such.one-P.INAN

    ‘Yan asks and begs Pila such.’

Unlike the preverbal clitics, da- can be associated with a full form, though it still displays special syntax in that unlike English -n’t or ‘ll, for instance, it does not occur in the same place as the full form. Note also how da- is appended to the right of tense prefixes, which express a property of the verb, as shown in (15).

    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      da-məpinyaya
      da-mə-pinya-ya.Ø
      so-PST-ask-3SG.M.TOP
      sa
      sa
      P
      Pila.
      Pila
      Pila

      ‘He asked Pila to.’
    2. Ang
      ang
      AT
      da-məpinyaya
      da-mə-pinya-ya.Ø
      so-PST-ask-3SG.M
      nay
      nay
      and
      məhisaya
      mə-hisa-ya.Ø
      PST-beg-3SG.M
      sa
      sa
      TOP
      Pila.
      Pila
      Yan

      ‘Yan asked and begged Pila to.’

The verb from in (15) becomes ungrammatical with the order of its prefixes reversed, so it is not acceptable to say: * məda-pinyaya, although note that pre- and suffixes proper also have a fixed order in Ayeri, so this alone is not enough evidence to claim that da- is not possibly a prefix. Furthermore, while the tense prefixes undergo crasis, this is not the case with da-:

    1. Da-amangreng.
      da-amang-reng
      thus-happen-3SG.INAN.A

      ‘It happens thus.’
    2. * Dāmangreng.
    1. Māmangreng.
      mÉ™-amang-reng
      PST-happen-3SG.INAN.A

      ‘It happened.’
    2. * Məamangreng.

Besides the characteristic of not seeking out certain parts of speech, the da- prefix at least satisfies the criteria of being a phonologically reduced form of an otherwise free functional morpheme, and it occurs in a place where normal syntax would not put its corresponding full form. It has wide scope over conjuncts, is attached outside of inflection for proper categories of the verb, and doesn’t interact with its host with regards to morphophonemics. Besides these more typical traits of clitics, there is also no way to place words between da- and the verb stem:

  1. *
    Da,
    da
    thus
    naratang,
    nara-tang
    say-3PL.M.A
    amangreng.
    amang-reng
    happen-3SG.INAN.A

    Intended: ‘It happens, they say, thus.’

The prefix sitang- ‘self’ behaves in the same way as da-, since it also abbreviates a reflexive NP, for instance, sitang-yes ‘herself’ where ‘herself’ as a patient is coreferential with the agent of the clause. Reflexivity, however, is a category a verb in Ayeri could be said to inflect for that way, though Ayeri also does not have any verbs which are obligatorily reflexive to indicate anticausativity like in Romance languages:

    1. Adruara
      adru-ara
      break-3SG.INAN
      biratayreng.
      biratay-reng
      pot-A.INAN

      ‘The pot broke.’3
    2. * 
      Sitang-adruara
      sitang-adru-ara
      self-break-3SG.INAN
      biratayreng.
      biratay-reng
      pot-A.INAN
    1. [French]
    2. Le
      le
      the
      pot
      pot
      pot
      sest
      se=est
      self=be.3SG.PRES
      cassé.
      cassé
      broken

      ‘The pot broke.’ (an unspecified force broke it)
    3. Le
      le
      the
      pot
      pot
      pot
      est
      est
      be.3SG.PRES
      cassé.
      cassé
      broken

      ‘The pot is broken.’

Ayeri has a tendency to reuse prefixes with different parts of speech, and thus da- is also used with nouns, forming part of the series of deictic prefixes, da- ‘such (a)’, eda- ‘this’, ada- ‘that’. The prefix in all these cases represents a grammatical function, is unstressed, and may have wide scope over conjoined NPs, unless an individuating interpretation is intended, as in (21b). These traits are typical of clitics, as we have seen, though (22) shows that unlike with verbs, the deictic prefixes do undergo crasis here, which is a trait more typically associated with affixes.

    1. Sinyāng
      sinya-ang
      who-A
      eda-ledanas
      eda-ledan-as
      this-friend-P
      nay
      nay
      and
      viretāyās
      viretāya-as
      supporter-P
      tondayena-hen?
      tonday-ena-hen
      art-GEN-all

      ‘Who is this friend and supporter of all arts?’
    2. Sinyāng
      sinya-ang
      who-A
      eda-ledanas
      eda-ledan-as
      this-friend-P
      nay
      nay
      and
      eda-viretāyās
      eda-viretāya-as
      this-supporter-P
      tondayena-hen?
      tonday-ena-hen
      art-GEN-all

      ‘Who is/are this friend and this supporter of all arts?’
  1. Sa
    sa
    PT
    ming
    ming
    can
    nelnang
    nel-nang
    help-1PL.A
    edāyon.
    eda-ayon-Ø
    this-man-TOP

    ‘This man, we can help him.’

The deictic prefixes also cannot be used with all types of NPs, only with those headed by generic and proper nouns; the picky nature of the deictic prefixes also makes them more typical of affixes than of clitics. The preverbal particles, on the other hand, also only occur with verbs, and I’ve nonetheless argued for them being clitics above.

As mentioned initially, Spencer and Luís (2012) give numerous counterexamples to the catalog of traits typically associated with clitics. One of this counterexample is what they term ‘suspended affixation’, which occurs in Turkish, for instance, where the plural suffix -lEr and subsequent suffixes can be left out in coordination (23a), as well as case markers (23b), and adverbials with case-like functions (23c):

    1. [Turkish]

      bütün
      all
      kitap(…)
      book
      ve
      and
      defter-ler-imiz
      notebook-PL-1PL.POSS

      ‘all our books and notebooks’ (199)
    2. Vapur
      boat
      hem
      and
      Napoli(…)
      Naples
      hem
      and
      Venedik’-e
      Venice-LOC
      uÄŸruyormuÅŸ
      stops.EVIDENTIAL

      ‘Apparently the boat stops at both Naples and Venice’ (ibid.)
    3. öğretmen-ler(…)
      teacher-PL
      ve
      and
      öğrenci-ler-le
      student-PL-WITH

      ‘with (the) students and (the) teachers’ (ibid.)

They note that, in “the nominal domain especially, wide scope inflection is widespread in the languages of Eurasia, becoming more prominent from west to east”, and that wide scope affixation “can be found with inflectional and derivational morphology in a number of languages, and it is often a symptom of recent and not quite complete morphologization” (200). They report Wälchli (2005) to find that this is especially the case with ‘natural coordination’, that is, the combination of items very frequently occurring in pairs like knife and fork or mother and father, as opposed to cases of occasional coordination (Spencer and Luís 2012: 200). Whether this is also true for Ayeri would require a separate survey.4

Given the evidence from Turkish, the categorization of deictic prefixes as either affixes or clitics is unclear, especially since the diagnostic of scope is devalued by the Turkish examples. On the other hand, suffixes on nouns don’t behave this way, as demonstrated in (24)—they rather behave like typical affixes in that they mandatorily occur on each conjunct. The question is, thus, whether an exception should be made for prefixes on nouns. We may as well assume that they are clitics.

    1. sobayajang
      sobaya-ye-ang
      teacher-PL-A
      nay
      nay
      and
      lajāyjang
      lajāy-ye-ang
      student-PL-A

      ‘(the) teachers and (the) students’
    2. * 
      sobayaye
      sobaya-ye
      teacher-PL
      nay
      nay
      and
      lajāyjang
      lajāy-ye-ang
      student-PL-A
    3. * 
      sobaya
      sobaya
      teacher
      nay
      nay
      and
      lajāyjang
      lajāy-ye-ang
      student-PL-A

From a functional point of view, the exact nature of the deictic prefixes shouldn’t matter either way—ParGram also cites a [DEIXIS] feature with PROXIMAL and DISTAL as its values, which fits eda- ‘this’ and ada- ‘that’ just fine. At present I’m at a loss about the feature representation of ‘such (a)’, however, since it is clearly deictic, but neither proximal nor distal. In this case it should be possible to just use [DEIXIS this/that/such] as well, I suppose, hence:

    1. edāyon
      eda-ayon
      this-man

      ‘this man’
    2. PRED ‘man’
      DEIXIS this

As described above, proper nouns are case marked by probably clitic case markers in front of the noun. In fact, these markers are somewhere at the left periphery of the NP, so the deictic prefixes stand in between the case marker and the proper noun itself, which is unproblematic for lexical integrity, since the deictic prefixes are not free morphemes. And even if they were part of inflection, the case markers, as clitics, would be on the outside—the order deictic prefix – case marker – noun is ungrammatical. An example is given in (26).

    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      koronay
      koron-ay.Ø
      know-1SG.TOP
      sa
      sa
      P
      eda-​kagan.
      eda-​kagan
      this-Kagan

      ‘I know this Kagan.’
    2. * 
      Ang
      ang
      AT
      koronay
      koron-ay.Ø
      know-1SG.TOP
      eda-​kaganas.
      eda-​kagan-as
      this-Kagan-P
    3. * 
      Ang
      ang
      AT
      koronay
      koron-ay.Ø
      know-1SG.TOP
      eda-sa
      eda-sa
      this-P
      Kagan.
      Kagan
      Kagan

The question now is, what happens to coordinated proper nouns? Since the suffixed case markers on common nouns have the distributional properties of affixes, they occur on every conjunct, the deictic prefix, however, only occurs on the first unless an individuating reading is intended, as shown in (20). For proper nouns it ought to be possible for both a case marker and a deictic prefix to have scope over coordinated proper nouns (27a). Yet, however, my gut tells me that this is slightly odd-sounding (German/English bias?), so I would prefer the strategy in (27b), which avoids the problem altogether by making the names an adjunct to the demonstrative edanya ‘this/these one(s)’.5 The example in (27c) is unproblematic and here as well indicates that the two people are referred to individually and not as a group.

    1. ? 
      Ang
      ang
      AT
      koronay
      koron-ay.Ø
      know-1SG.TOP
      sa
      sa
      P
      eda-​Kagan
      eda-​Kagan
      this-​Kagan
      nay
      nay
      and
      Ijān.
      Ijān
      Ijān

      ‘I know these Kagan and Ijān.’
    2. Ang
      ang
      AT
      koronay
      koron-ay.Ø
      know-1SG.TOP
      edanyās,
      edanya-as
      this.one-P
      Kagan
      Kagan
      Kagan
      nay
      nay
      and
      Ijān.
      Ijān
      Ijān

      ‘I know these, Kagan and Ijān.’
    3. Ang
      ang
      AT
      koronay
      koron-ay.Ø
      know-1SG.TOP
      sa
      sa
      P
      eda-​Kagan
      eda-​Kagan
      this-​Kagan
      nay
      nay
      and
      eda-​Ijān.
      eda-​Ijān
      this-​Ijān

      ‘I know this Kagan and this Ijān.’

Of the deictic prefixes, da- is not only available to verbs and nouns, but also to adjectives. Like with verbs, it is short for danya ‘such one’ in this case (28a). The resulting meaning is ‘the adj. one’; da- essentially acts as a nominalizer, at least to the extent the compound of da- + adjective inherits the distributional properties of danya as a demonstrative pronoun. Thus, it can be case- and topic marked (28bc), and also be modified by another adjective (28c). On the other hand, it can’t be reduplicated for diminution, and also also can’t be pluralized. Since adjectives follow their heads, the original order of demonstrative – adjective remains intact.

    1. Le
      le
      PT.INAN
      noyang
      no-yang
      want-1SG.A
      danyaley
      danya-Ø
      such.one-TOP
      tuvo.
      tuvo
      red

      ‘The red one I want.’
    2. Ang
      ang
      AT
      noay
      no-ay.Ø
      want-1SG.TOP
      da-tuvoley.
      da-tuvo-ley
      one-red-P.INAN

      ‘I want the red one.’
    3. Le
      le
      PT.INAN
      noyang
      no-yang
      want-1SG.A
      da-tuvo
      da-tuvo-Ø
      small
      kivo.
      kivo

      ‘The little red one I want.’

The prefix, again, coheres tightly in that no additional material can be inserted. Like with nouns above, inflecting each form in a group of coordinated adjectives results in an individuating reading (29a). It should be possible for the prefix to take wide scope (29b), though it seems better to me to instead rephrase the coordinated adjective as a relative clause (28c), for instance, besides using the full form danya + adjectives. Since case markers go on every conjunct, (29d) is not grammatical.

    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      noay
      no-ay.Ø
      want-1SG.TOP
      da-tuvoley
      da-tuvo-ley
      one-red-P.INAN
      nay
      nay
      and
      da-lenoley.
      da-leno-ley
      one-blue-P.INAN

      ‘I want the blue one and the red one.’
    2. ? 
      Ang
      ang
      AT
      noay
      no-ay.Ø
      want-1SG.TOP
      da-tuvoley
      da-tuvo-ley
      one-red-P.INAN
      nay
      nay
      and
      lenoley.
      leno-ley
      blue-P.INAN

      ‘I want the red and blue one.’
    3. Ang
      ang
      AT
      noay
      no-ay.Ø
      want-1SG.TOP
      adaley
      ada-ley
      that-P.INAN
      si
      si
      REL
      tuvo
      tuvo
      red
      nay
      nay
      and
      leno.
      leno
      blue

      ‘I want that which is red and blue.’
    4. * 
      Ang
      ang
      AT
      noay
      no-ay.Ø
      want-1SG.TOP
      da-tuvo
      da-tuvo
      one-red
      nay
      nay
      and
      lenoley.
      leno-ley
      blue-P.INAN

Possessive pronouns like nā ‘my’, vana ‘your’, etc. behave the same way when derived to free-standing anaphora (da-nā ‘mine’, da-vana ‘yours’, etc.) from their usual role as modifiers, except they can’t themselves be modified by adjectives in the way da-tuvo ‘the red one’ is in (28c). Taking all of the examples above into account, da- with adjectives and possessive pronouns seems to be most like a simple clitic according to Zwicky’s (1977) definition, compared to the other contexts it can appear in:

Cases where a free morpheme, when unaccented, may be phonologically subordinated to a neighboring word. Cliticization of this sort is usually associated with stylistic conditions, as in the casual speech cliticization of object pronouns in English; there are both formal full pronouns and casual reduced pronouns. (Zwicky 1977: 5)

Typical of a simple clitic as well, the distribution of da- is restricted by grammatical context, as pointed out regarding example (27b). Unlike in English, which Zwicky (1977) gives examples of, the condition in Ayeri is likely not phonological in this case. The nature of the condition, however, is not predetermined in Spencer and Luís (2012), when they write that

we may therefore need to define simple clitics along the lines of Halpern (1998), namely, as clitics that may be positioned in a subset of the positions within which the full forms are found, rather than as clitics that have the same distribution as their full-form counterparts as in Zwicky (1977). Under this broader definition, we capture the fact that simple clitics differ from special clitics in that they can appear in some of the positions that are occupied by their corresponding full forms, while special clitics never can. (Spencer and Luís 2012: 44)

Besides deictic prefixes, nouns may also receive a prefix expressing likeness, ku-. This prefix is also applicable to adjectives, and is maybe more adverbial in terms of semantics than purely functional morphemes like da-. In contrast to da-, ku- has no full-form equivalent. Some examples of it leaning on nouns are given in (30). Like the deictic prefixes, ku- appears in a position which is privileged to dependent functional morphemes in that any modifiers which appear as free words or phrases (adjectives, relative clauses, nominal adjuncts) follow nouns. Slightly untypical of a clitic, it is not fully ‘promiscuous’ regarding its phonological host in that it requires a nominal, adjectival or phrasal host.

    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      misya
      mis-ya
      act-3SG.M
       
      Ø
      TOP
      Amān
      Amān
      Amān
      ku-depangas.
      ku-depang-as
      like-fool-P

      ‘Amān acts like a fool.’
    2. Ang
      ang
      AT
      misya
      mis-ya
      act-3SG.M
       
      Ø
      TOP
      Amān
      Amān
      Amān
      ku-depangas
      ku-depang-as
      like-fool-P
      nay
      nay
      and
      karayās.
      karaya-as
      coward-P

      ‘Amān acts like a fool and a coward.’
    3. Ang
      ang
      AT
      misya
      mis-ya
      act-3SG.M
       
      Ø
      TOP
      Amān
      Amān
      Amān
      ku-depangas
      ku-depang-as
      like-fool-P
      nay
      nay
      and
      ku-karayās.
      ku-karaya-as
      ku-coward-P

      ‘Amān acts like a fool and like a coward.’
    4. Ang
      ang
      AT
      misya
      mis-ya
      act-3SG.M
       
      Ø
      TOP
      Amān
      Amān
      Amān
      ku-ada-depangas.
      ku-ada-depang-as
      like-that-fool-P

      ‘Amān acts like that fool.’
    5. Ang
      ang
      AT
      misya
      mis-ya
      act-3SG.M
       
      Ø
      TOP
      Amān
      Amān
      Amān
      ku-ada-depangas
      ku-ada-depang-as
      like-that-fool-P
      nay
      nay
      and
      ada-karayās.
      ada-karayās
      that-coward-P

      ‘Amān acts like that fool and that coward.’
    6. * 
      Ang
      ang
      AT
      misya
      mis-ya
      act-3SG.M
       
      Ø
      TOP
      Amān
      Amān
      Amān
      ada-ku-depangas.
      ada-ku-depang-as
      that-like-fool-P

Generally, ku- fulfills the function of the preposition like in English in (30). However, if it were a preposition in Ayeri, it should trigger the locative on its dependent. In the examples above, however, the NP ku- modifies takes the patient case, like predicative NPs are otherwise wont to do. While prepositions like kong ‘inside’ in (31) are free morphemes in Ayeri, ku- is bound, which becomes apparent by introducing a parenthetical remark again:

    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      yomāy,
      yoma-ay.Ø
      be-1SG.TOP
      surpareng,
      surpa-reng
      seem-3SG.INAN
      kong
      kong
      inside
      sayanya.
      sayan-ya
      cave-LOC

      ‘I am, it seems, inside a cave.’
    2. Ang
      ang
      AT
      yomāy
      yoma-ay.Ø
      be-1SG.TOP
      kong,
      kong
      inside
      suprareng,
      surpa-reng
      seem-3SG.INAN
      sayanya.
      sayan-ya
      cave-LOC

      ‘I’m inside, it seems, a cave.’
    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      misya
      mis-ya
      act-3SG.M
       
      Ø
      TOP
      Amān,
      Amān
      Amān
      surpareng,
      surpa-reng
      seem-3SG.INAN
      ku-depangas.
      ku-depang-as
      like-fool-P

      ‘Amān acts, it seems, like a fool.’
    2. * 
      Ang
      ang
      AT
      misya
      mis-ya
      act-3SG.M
       
      Ø
      TOP
      Amān
      Amān
      Amān
      ku,
      ku
      like
      surpareng,
      surpa-reng
      seem-3SG.INAN
      depangas.
      depang-as
      fool-P

      ‘Amān acts like a, it seems, fool.’

Examples (30ab) show that similar to the deictic prefixes, ku- precedes its target of modification and can have wide scope with coordinated NPs. As (30c) shows, narrow scope is possible as well, and in this case, again, each conjunct is to be interpreted separately instead of ku- modifying both conjuncts collectively. If combined with ada- as a deictic prefix, for instance, ku- even precedes that (30d), and changing the order of the prefixes is not possible, as is shown in (30f). As (30e) shows, ku- may also have scope over two individuating noun phrase conjuncts. Ku- is also applicable to pronouns, so (33) is possible, for example.

    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      silvye
      silv-ye
      look-3SG.F
       
      Ø
      TOP
      Pada
      Pada
      Pada
      ku-yes.
      ku-yes
      like-3SG.F.P

      ‘Pada looks like her.’
    2. Sa
      sa
      PT
      silvye
      silv-ye
      look-3SG.F
      ang
      ang
      A
      Pada
      Pada
      Pada
      ku-ye.
      ku-ye
      like-3SG.F.TOP

      ‘Like her Pada looks.’

With proper nouns, we get the same distributional properties as with generic nouns, except that ku- appears (rather idiosyncratically) as a suffix at the right edge of an NP—or at the right edge of the first NP conjunct—if the NP is preceded by a case marker, as shown in (34). Admittedly, I hadn’t considered the behavior of ku- with names before and felt adventurous in introducing this little twist. I hope it’s viable.

    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      lentava
      lenta-va
      sound-2.TOP
      sa
      sa
      P
      Tagāti
      Tagāti
      Tagāti
      diyan-ku.
      diyan-ku
      worthy-like

      ‘You sound like Mr. Tagāti.’
    2. Ang
      ang
      AT
      lentava
      lenta-va
      sound-2.TOP
      sa
      sa
      P
      Tagāti
      Tagāti
      Tagāti
      diyan-ku
      diyan-ku
      worthy-like
      nay
      nay
      and
      diranas
      diran-as
      uncle-P
      yana.
      yana
      3SG.M.GEN

      ‘You sound like Mr. Tagāti and his uncle.’
    3. Sa
      sa
      PT
      lentavāng
      lenta-vāng
      sound-2.A
      ku-​Tagāti
      ku-​Tagāti
      like-​Tagāti
      diyan.
      diyan
      worthy

      ‘Like Mr. Tagāti you sound.’

With adjectives, however, there are no idiosyncrasies to this degree; ku- appears only as a prefix here, as with generic nouns:

    1. Surpya
      surp-ya
      seem-3SG.M
      ku-suta
      ku-suta
      like-busy
      ang
      ang
      A
      Maran.
      Maran
      Maran

      ‘Maran seems like he’s busy.’
    2. Surpya
      surp-ya
      seem-3SG.M
      ku-suta
      ku-suta
      like-busy
      nay
      nay
      and
      baras
      baras
      gruff
      ang
      ang
      A
      Maran.
      Maran
      Maran

      ‘Maran seems like he’s busy and gruff.’

As (35b) shows, ku- again can have wide scope over conjuncts. What further distinguishes ku- from a prefix here is that it doesn’t undergo crasis if the adjective begins with an /u/, hence ku-ubo /kuˈubo/ ‘like bitter’, not * kÅ«bo /ˈkuːbo/.6 Again, the position ku- appears in is special in that whatever modifies adjectives usually trails after them.

Another case I hadn’t considered before is that ku- should be able to subordinate infinite CPs. Since ku- leans on a whole phrase in (35), which affixes can’t do, its status as a clitic should be unmistakable in this context.

  1. Silvyeng
    silv-yeng
    look-3SG.F.A
    ku-tahayam
    ku-taha-yam
    like-have-PTCP
    misungas.
    misung-as
    secret-P

    ‘She looks as though having a secret.’

2. Suffixes

I hope that I could shed some light on the prefixes and particles occuring before lexical heads so far, however, Ayeri also has a number of morphemes trailing lexical heads as suffixes which do not seem quite like typical inflection. These are, for one, person suffixes on the verb, which I already tried to come to terms with in a previous blog article. In this article, I had assumed a priori that the case- and topic-marked suffixes on the verb are clitics. However, what I didn’t do is to test whether they actually fulfill formal criteria of clitics. Especially tricky in this regard is maybe that “a pronominal affix or incorporated pronominal is effectively a clitic masquerading as an affix. Therefore, if there are pronominal affixes then they should behave exactly like clitics with respect to crucial aspects of morphosyntax” (Spencer and Luís 2012: 144). Spencer and Luís (2012) then proceed to give examples from Breton and Irish where the person marking on the verb is in complementary distribution with full NPs:

    1. [Breton]
    2. Bremañ
      now
      e
      PRT
      lennont
      read.PRES.3PL
      al
      the
      levrioù
      books

      ‘Now they are reading the books’ (145, from Borsley et al. 2007)
    3. Bremañ
      now
      e
      PRT
      lenn
      read.PRES.3SG
      ar
      the
      vugale
      children
      al
      the
      levrioù
      books

      ‘Now the children are reading the books’ (ibid.)
    4. * 
      Bremañ
      now
      e
      PRT
      lennont
      read.PRES.3PL
      ar
      the
      vugale
      children
      al
      the
      levrioù
      books

      (ibid.)
    1. [Irish]
    2. Chuirfinn
      put.COND.1SG
      (*mé)
      (​I​)
      isteach
      in
      ar
      on
      an
      the
      phost
      job
      sin
      that

      ‘I would apply for that job’ (145, from McCloskey and Hale 1984)
    3. Chuirfeadh
      put.COND.3SG
      sibh
      you
      isteach
      in
      ar
      on
      an
      the
      phost
      job
      sin
      that

      ‘You would apply for that job’ (ibid.)
    4. Chuirfeadh
      put.COND.3SG
      Eoghan
      Owen
      isteach
      in
      ar
      on
      an
      the
      phost
      job
      sin
      that

      ‘Owen would apply for that job’ (ibid.)

What we can see in (37) is that, according to Spencer and Luís (2012), the verb shows no number marking, defaulting to the singular form, in non-negative clauses if the subject of the verb is overt as either a full noun or a pronoun: plural marking on the verb and a full subject can’t coincide in this case, which is why (37c) is marked ungrammatical. In (38a) we can see that there is no need for an explicit first-person pronoun, since that function is already expressed by person marking on the verb—person inflection on the verb seems to be in complementary distribution with full subject pronouns at least for some parts of the paradigm. In (38b) we have an overt 2nd-person subject pronoun, but in this case, the verb does not agree with it and instead defaults to the 3rd-person form, a clear case of which is given in (38c).

While in Ayeri, there is no defaulting to a certain person in the presence of an overt subject NP as such, there is still the effect of complementary distribution between a pronominal suffix in the absence of an overt subject NP and a functionally impoverished as well as phonologically reduced form in its presence:

    1. Suta
      suta
      busy
      ang
      ang
      A
      Niyas.
      Niyas
      Niyas

      ‘Niyas is busy.’
    2. Yāng
      yāng
      3SG.M.A
      suta.
      suta
      busy

      ‘He is busy.’
    1. Lampya
      lamp-ya
      walk-3SG.M
      ang
      ang
      A
      Niyas.
      Niyas
      Niyas

      ‘Niyas is walking.’
    2. Lampyāng.
      lamp-yāng
      walk-3SG.M.A

      ‘He is walking’
    1. * 
      Lampyāng
      lamp-yang
      walk-3SG.M.A
      ang
      ang
      A
      Niyas.
      Niyas
      Niyas
    2. * 
      Lampya
      lamp-ya
      walk-3SG.M
      yāng.
      yāng
      3SG.M.A

Example (39b) shows the free form of the third singular masculine agent pronoun, yāng. This is in complementary distribution with a full NP, which in (39a) is ang Niyas. In (40a) we can see that the verb agrees with the subject NP in person, gender and number in that it exhibits the suffix -ya. If the overt subject NP is missing, the verb is marked with the same form as the free pronoun, -yāng, which feeds the verb as a syntactic argument. That is, the person suffix itself fills the SUBJ relation of the verb’s subcategorization frame. (42) lists the constituent parts of lampyāng and their associated grammatical features.

  1. lamp- Vstem (↑ PRED) = ‘walk ⟨(↑ SUBJ)⟩’
    -yāng Vinfl (↑ PRED) = ‘pro’
    (↑ PERS) = 3
    (↑ NUM) = SG
    (↑ GEND) = M
    (↑ ANIM) = +
    (↑ CASE) = A
  2. PRED ‘walk ⟨(↑ SUBJ)⟩’
    SUBJ
    PRED ‘pro’
    PERS 3
    NUM SG
    GEND M
    ANIM +
    CASE A

Since (43) shows that functionally, the inflection takes the role of the subject relation, (41a) is ungrammatical in that the pronominal suffix -yāng on the verb is redundant in the presence of a full NP which expresses the same features except that the subject NP’s [PRED] value is ‘Niyas’, not ‘pro’. Example (44) shows the annotations for lampya as agreeing with an overt NP. Here, the suffix does not have a [PRED] feature–it is not available for predication. The semantic features of -ya are also not defined (=), but required by constraint (=c), that is, the morpheme constrains the presence of an NP which defines these features and with which the verb thus agrees—the overt subject NP, which is the agent NP in canonical cases. By requiring that the subject’s predicator not be a pro-form in (44) it should be possible to rule out cases like in (41b), where person agreement is triggered by a pronominal NP, which is ungrammatical, since Ayeri basically supplants person agreement with a pronominal suffix in those cases. If -yāng were a simple inflectional affix, one of the two examples in (39) should be grammatical.

  1. -ya₁ Vinfl (↑ SUBJ PRED) =c ¬ ’pro’
    (↑ SUBJ PERS) =c 3
    (↑ SUBJ NUM) =c SG
    (↑ SUBJ GEND) =c M
    (↑ SUBJ ANIM) =c +

The behavior of the pronominal person marking on the verb is thus rather complex, and decidedly unlike inflection in that what looks like an affix on the verb is also an argument of it, like a pronoun, as displayed in (42). Another layer of complexity is added by the fact that such an incorporated pronoun is also eligible for topicalization. As we have seen above, topic marking on nouns is realized by suppressing the realization of the overt case marker, whether it is a proclitic or a suffix. The topic-marked forms of pronouns are also underspecified for case, and they happen to be the same as those of the person-agreement suffixes as exemplified by -ya in (40a). Thus, a topic-marked pronominal suffix on the verb will look exactly like ordinary agreement with a full NP, except that there is no full NP to agree with—hence the subscript numbers in (44) and (45) to distinguish between both kinds of -ya.7

  1. -yaâ‚‚ Vinfl (↑ PRED) = ‘pro’
    (↑ PERS) = 3
    (↑ NUM) = SG
    (↑ GEND) = M
    (↑ ANIM) = +
    (↑ CASE) = Ø ⇒ (↑ TOP) = ↓

Comparing the feature list in (45) with that in (42) and (44), we see that (45) is basically the same as (42), except that either the [CASE] feature is not set, or that the suffix is underspecified for case. In absence of an NP to agree with, it follows from this definitional lack that the person marking on the verb itself is to be identified as constituting the topic, and the correspondent of the preverbal topic marker. In the following case, the preverbal topic marker defines that the topic is an animate agent:

  1. ang Cl (↑ TOP CASE) = A
    (↑ TOP ANIM) = +

Instances of other case-unmarked nouns can be ruled out as being also part of the topic relation on the grounds of cohesion: if the topic is defined as an agent and it can’t be assumed from context that the case-unmarked noun in question is also part of the agent NP, discard it as a candidate. Besides, every core θ-role (agent, patient, recipient) can only be assigned once, so if the role specified by the topic marker is already assigned, another NP in the same clause can’t also be assigned it. This gets more difficult with non-core roles, though I assume that oblique arguments are less likely to be topicalized.

What has led me to confusion about the status of the pronominal suffixes in the past is essentially that “a pronominal affix or incorporated pronominal is effectively a clitic masquerading as an affix” (Spencer and Luís 2012: 144). While the pronominal suffixes in Ayeri behave in a special way regarding syntax, they lack wide scope, which is typical of affixes (apart from the examples from Turkish quoted earlier). Unlike Breton or Irish, Ayeri’s pronominal affixes do not default to some form, and verbs cannot be unmarked either, that is, verbs always have to be inflected in some way, mostly for phonotactic reasons. Thus, in coordination, every conjunct has to be inflected for person features:

    1. Nedrayāng
      nedra-yāng
      sit-3SG.M.A
      nay
      nay
      and
      layayāng.
      laya-yāng
      read-3SG.M.A

      ‘He is sitting and reading.’
    2. * 
      Nedrayāng
      nedra-yāng
      sit-3SG.M.A
      nay
      nay
      and
      laya.
      laya
      read
    3. * 
      Nedra
      nedra
      sit
      nay
      nay
      and
      layayāng.
      laya-yāng
      read-3SG.M.A

In the case of nedra- and laya- in (47), leaving off the person marking would theoretically work, since * nedra and * laya satisfy phonotactic constraints. However, Ayeri also has a great number of verb stems which end in a consonant cluster, such as anl- ‘bring’ or tapy- ‘set’, which don’t form valid words as bare stems. What would be possible instead is that one conjunct might carry the full pronominal suffix as a “strong” form and the other one might only partially co-index the required features by using the less specific corresponding agreement marker as a “weak” form. Differential marking of this kind, though, is simply not established.

After briefly delving into the realm of syntax, let’s return to morphology for the second group of suffixes which could use some clarification. While Ayeri has quantifiers which are independent words, there are also a number of very common ‘little’ quantifiers and degree adverbs which are customarily spelled as suffixes, for instance, -ikan ‘much, many; very’, -kay ‘few; a little’, -nama ‘almost’, -nyama ‘even’. All of these are adverbial in meaning and while they are comparatively light in their semantics compared to regular content words, I can’t say that they strike me as functional morphemes in particular. In the course of writing this article, an article which has come up in my searches a number of times is Bittner (1995) on quantification in West Greenlandic. According to her terminology, -ikan in Ayeri would be a D-quantifier, which “forms a constituent with, a projection of N” (Bittner 1995: 59), in contrast to A-quantifiers, which form “a constituent with some projection of V” (59). That is, A-quantifiers are adverbs like almost (-nama in Ayeri), mostly, or never, while D-quantifiers are words like most, some, or every. Ayeri makes no distinction between A- and D-quantifiers with regards to their being treated as suffixes, so one can find suffixed quantifiers in both groups. While my main interest here is in the morphosyntax of these quantifiers, Bittner’s is in their semantics, though the article gives evidence notwithstanding of a language in which suffixed quantifiers are attested, for example:

  1. [West Greenlandic]
    1. qaatuur-tuaanna-ngajap-p-a-a
      break-always-almost-IND-TR-3SG₁.3SG₂

      ‘he almost always breaks it’ (adapted from Bittner 1995: 60)
    2. qaqutigu-rujussuaq
      rarely-very

      ‘very rarely’ (63)
    1. ang
      ang
      AT
      adruya
      adru-ya.Ø
      break-3SG.M.TOP
      tadayen-ngas
      tadayen-ngas
      always-almost
      adaley
      ada-ley
      that-P.INAN

      ‘he almost always breaks it’
    2. kora-ikan
      rarely-very

      ‘very rarely’

As we can see in (48a), West Greenlandic incorporates the quantifier suffixes into the verb, while Ayeri—not a polysynthetic language—proceeds more freely in (49a) in that tadayen ‘always, every time’ is an adverb and as such a free morpheme which is, however, in turn modified by a suffixed quantifier. Since orthography may be treacherous, let’s first try to establish whether -ngas and -ikan and their like are free morphemes or not. As discussed initially regarding the preverbal particles, it is possible to reorder free morphemes, while clitics, as bound morphemes, can’t move around. Adverbs and adjectives are, if they optionally add additional information to a lexical head, adjuncts, and according to Carnie (2013) it is possible for adjuncts to switch places within the same syntactic domain. Adjuncts can also be coordinated with other adjuncts in the same syntactic domain. Furthermore, it is possible to replace X’ nodes with pro-forms, like one in English.

    1. kipisānye-ikan
      kipisān-ye-ikan
      painting-PL-many
      bino
      bino
      colorful
      kāryo
      kāryo
      big

      ‘many big colorful paintings’
    2. kipisānye-ikan kāryo bino
      ‘many big colorful paintings’
    3. ! kipisānye bino-ikan kāryo
      ‘very colorful big paintings’
    4. ! kipisānye bino kāryo-ikan
      ‘very big colorful paintings’
    1. kipisānye-ikan
      kipisān-ye-ikan
      painting-PL-many
      bino
      bino
      colorful
      nay
      nay
      and
      kāryo
      kāryo
      big

      ‘many big and colorful paintings’
    2. * kipisānye-ikan nay bino kāryo
      ‘many and colorful big paintings’
    3. ! kipisānye bino-ikan nay kāryo
      ‘big and very colorful paintings’

As (50cd) shows, moving -ikan ‘many, much, very’ into different positions results not necessarily in ungrammatical expressions, but in ones with meanings different from what was intended, since -ikan‘s scope changes from the noun to the adjective it is appended to. On the other hand, comparing (50a) and (b), it is possible for kāryo ‘big’ and bino ‘colorful’ to switch places with no adversary effects. Example (51b) demonstrates that placing a coordinating conjunction between -ikan and bino ‘colorful’ doesn’t work. The coordination in (51c), on the other hand, is not a problem—not because it is possible to coordinate -ikan and kāryo, but because bino-ikan ‘very colorful’ is considered one syntactic unit which is coordinated with kāryo. Thus, in (50b), we have actually been trying to coordinate kipisānye-ikan ‘many paintings’ with bino ‘colorful’, which does not work, since it is not possible to coordinate a lexical head with an adjunct supposed to modify it, since they are of different syntactic categories. In this regard it is worth mentioning that Ayeri’s quantifier suffixes are rather not complements either, since they are not required in order to satisfy their head’s argument structure.

One might argue that in (50) and (51) we tried to compare apples to oranges in that -ikan and bino are of different categories, since -ikan and bino don’t appear to operate on the same levels. So instead, let’s look at possibilities of word order change and coordination between different quantifiers to ensure that we actually stay on the same level. With this there is the problem, however, that it seems strange to modify the same lexical head with multiple different quantifiers, so this test does not really seem feasible to produce grammatical results. Also, with regards to coordination of quantifiers, it is maybe more natural to oppose them with soyang ‘or’ than to coordinate them; the grammatical structure of two categorially identical elements connected by a grammatical conjunction (even if the meaning is disjunctive) remains the same in either case.

    1. * 
      keynam-ikan-kay
      keynam-ikan-kay
      people-many-few

      ‘few many people’
    2. ? 
      keynam-ikan
      keynam-ikan
      people-many
      soyang
      soyang
      or
      -kay
      -kay
      few

      ‘few or many people’

In example (52a) we see that it is indeed not possible to combine multiple quantifiers to jointly modify a head in the way it is possible for multiple adjectives to modify the same head as in (50a), for instance. The example of quantifier disjunction in (52b) is also odd unless we permit a reading where keynam ‘people’ has been suppressed in the second disjunct to avoid repetition, although in the corresponding case of (53b) below, da-kay would be preferable.

    1. ? keynam[-ikan soyang kay]
      ‘[few or many] people’
    2. [keynami-ikan] soyang [_i-kay]
      ‘[few _i] or [many peoplei]’

Both tests, moving -ikan into other positions and coordination, have failed so far, and we have evidence that -ikan forms a syntactic unit with its head, which points to it being a bound morpheme similar to an affix in spite of its adverb-like meaning. As with free words, it is also possible to replace a quantifier’s head with a pro-form, as mentioned above in the comment on (53b), and shown in more detail in (54). With quantifier suffixes there seems to be an overlap between word-like and affix-like properties, which is typical of clitics.

    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      vacyan
      vac-yan
      like-3SG.M
      keynam-ikan
      keynam-Ø-ikan
      people-TOP-many
      seygoley.
      seygo-ley.
      apple-P.INAN

      ‘Many people like apples.’
    2. Ang
      ang
      AT
      vacyan
      vac-yan
      like-3SG.M
      danya-ikan
      danya-Ø-ikan
      such.one-TOP-many
      seygoley.
      seygo-ley.
      apple-P.INAN

      ‘Many of them like apples.’
    3. Ang
      ang
      AT
      vacyan
      vac-yan
      like-3SG.M
      da-ikan
      da-ikan-Ø
      one-many-TOP
      seygoley.
      seygo-ley.
      apple-P.INAN

      ‘Many (of them) like apples.’

Somewhat untypical of affixes, it seems to be possible to modify suffixed quantifier with adverbs like ekeng ‘too’ and kagan ‘far too’, as (55) shows. This suggests that at least in this context, -ikan may actually be the lexical head of an adverbial phrase, which is at odds with its status as a bound morpheme.

  1. Ang
    ang
    AT
    vacyan
    vac-yan
    like-3SG.M
    keynam-ikan
    keynam-Ø-ikan
    people-TOP-many
    kagan
    kagan
    far.too
    disuley.
    disu-ley.
    disu-P.INAN

    ‘Far too many people like bananas.’

I previously tried to insert parenthetical word material in between morphemes, and this test may be especially interesting in face of (55), since here it is not entirely clear whether keynam-ikan kagan ‘too many people’ forms a single unit. Since signs point to the status of quantifier suffixes as clitics, chances are good that it does, in fact, constitute a clitic cluster similar to the preverbal one. Example (56), therefore, lists examples which try to split up the expression at every relevant point. According to this test, it looks indeed as though keynam-ikan kagan forms a syntactic unit, in that -ikan kagan ‘too many’ cannot be split up internally and also cannot be divided from -ikan‘s head, keynam ‘people’.

    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      vacyan,
      vac-yan
      like-3SG.M
      ​​narayang​​,
      nara-yang
      say-1SG.A
      keynam-ikan
      keynam-Ø-ikan
      people-TOP-many
      kagan
      kagan
      far.too
      disuley.
      disu-ley
      disu-P.INAN

      ‘Far too many people, I say, like bananas.’
    2. * Ang vacyan keynam, narayang, ikan kagan disuley.
    3. * Ang vacyan keynam-ikan, narayang, kagan disuley.
    4. Ang vacyan keynam-ikan kagan, narayang, disuley.

Another interesting distributional property of suffixed quantifiers in Ayeri is that in spite of their being suffixed, to verbs for instance, they can form arguments of the verb, similar to pronominal suffixes. Thus, with verbs like kond- ‘eat’, -ma ‘enough’ appears suffixed to the verb instead of as a predicative adverb. Incidentally, the examples in (56) also show that a quantifier attaches after pronominal suffixes, which we have already established as being clitics. An inflectional affix would not normally appear in post-clitic position, which is further evidence to the hypothesis that quantifier suffixes in Ayeri are clitics.

    1. Kondanang-ma.
      kond-nang-ma
      eat-1PL.A-enough

      ‘We ate enough.’
    2. Ang
      ang
      AT
      tangay-ikan
      tang-ay.Ø-ikan
      hear-1SG.TOP-much
      vana.
      vana
      2.GEN

      ‘I’ve heard much about you.’

Since Ayeri possesses a zero copula, equative phrases which treat quantifier suffixes as predicative adverbs pose a difficulty in that quantifier suffixes cannot stand alone like predicatives normally would. Thus, in a similar fashion to -ma‘s behavior in (57a), the predicative -ma in (58b) cliticizes to the only available word: the subject, adareng ‘that’.

    1. Adareng
      ada-reng
      that-A.INAN
      edaya.
      edaya
      here

      ‘It is here.’
    2. Adareng-ma.
      ada-reng-ma
      that-A.INAN-enough

      ‘That/It is enough.’

If quantifier suffixes are clitics, they should also have wide scope over conjuncts. Here as well, quantifier suffixes behave typically of clitics, though, in that they can have scope over a conjunct as a whole, although not totally unambiguously so.

    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      tahisayan
      tahisa-yan.Ø
      own-3PL.M.TOP
      koyās
      koya-as
      book-P
      nay
      nay
      and
      kihasley-ikan.
      kihas-ley-ikan
      map-P.INAN-many

      ‘They own many books and maps.’
    2. Yeng
      yeng
      3SG.F.A
      alingo
      alingo
      clever
      nay
      nay
      and
      para-ven.
      para-ven
      quick-pretty

      ‘She’s pretty clever and quick.’

Thus, in (59a), while koyās nay kihasley-ikan is translated as ‘many books and maps’ (nouns do not mark plural if modified by a quantifier which indicates plurality), another possible reading is ‘a book and many maps’. Ways to force the latter reading explicitly are, for one, to use koyās men ‘one/a single book’, or alternatively, to reduplicate the coordinator nay ‘and’ to naynay ‘and also’. Context should be sufficient to indicate the correct reading of (59a) under normal circustances, however. The same applies to (59b), where the non-distributive reading can be made explicit by using naynay instead of simple nay. In both (59a) and (b), if the first conjunct is modified by an adjective, the distribution of the quantifier over both conjuncts is also blocked. Thus, in (60a), there is ‘a big book and many maps’, and in (60b) ‘she’ is ‘surprisingly clever and pretty quick’.

    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      tahisayan
      tahisa-yan.Ø
      own-3PL.M.TOP
      koyās
      koya-as
      book-P
      kāryo
      kāryo
      big
      nay
      nay
      and
      kihasley-ikan.
      kihas-ley-ikan
      map-P.INAN-many

      ‘They own a big book and many maps.’
      Not: ‘They own many big books and maps.’
    2. Yeng
      yeng
      3SG.F.A
      alingo
      alingo
      clever
      patu
      patu
      surprisingly
      nay
      nay
      and
      para-ven.
      para-ven
      quick-pretty

      ‘She’s surprisingly clever and pretty quick.’
      Not: ‘She is surprisingly pretty clever and quick.’

The false interpretations in (60) can be correctly achieved by ordinarily placing the adjective after the compounds so that the adjective itself has scope over both conjuncts. This is demonstrated in (61) and (62). Again, an unambiguous and individuating interpretation can be achieved by placing the quantifier suffix on each conjunct.

    1. Ang
      ang
      AT
      tahisayan
      tahisa-yan.Ø
      own-3PL.M.TOP
      koyajas
      koya-ye-as
      book-PL-P
      nay
      nay
      and
      kihasyeley
      kihas-ye-ley
      map-PL-P.INAN
      kāryo.
      kāryo
      big

      ‘They own big books and maps.’
    2. Ang
      ang
      AT
      tahisayan
      tahisa-yan.Ø
      own-3PL.M.TOP
      koyās
      koya-as
      book-PL-P
      nay
      nay
      and
      kihasley-ikan
      kihas-ley-ikan
      map-P.INAN-many
      kāryo.
      kāryo
      big

      ‘They own many big books and maps.’
    1. Yeng
      yeng
      3SG.F.A
      alingo
      alingo
      clever
      nay
      nay
      and
      para
      para
      quick
      patu.
      patu
      surprisingly

      ‘She’s surprisingly clever and quick.’
    2. Yeng
      yeng
      3SG.F.A
      alingo
      alingo
      clever
      nay
      nay
      and
      para-ven
      para-ven
      quick-pretty
      patu.
      patu
      surprisingly

      ‘She’s surprisingly pretty clever and quick.’

3. Conclusive remarks

I have applied various tests, mostly of morphosyntactic nature, to particles occurring in front of verbs, nouns, and adjectives, as well as to suffixes indicating person features on verbs, and to quantifier suffixes on a variety of parts of speech in order test whether these particles, prefixes, and suffixes behave like clitics in spite of appearing like function words, adverbs, prefixes, or suffixes. By testing morphosyntactic properties of the various morphemes evidence was presented to argue that (1) the preverbal particles form a clitic cluster together with the verb; (2) da- and sitang- on verbs are likely clitics; (3) da- on nouns, adjectives and possessive pronouns are clitics; (4) the preposed case markers of names are likely clitics; (5) deictic prefixes on the noun are likely clitics; (6) pronominal suffixes on verbs are clitics for their special syntax and in spite of the suffixes’ narrow scope, which is at least in part due to phonotactic requirements; and (7), suffixed quantifiers are clitics in spite of their adverbial meaning.

  • Bittner, Maria. “Quantification in Eskimo: A Challenge for Compositional Semantics.” Quantification in Natural Languages. Ed. by Emmon Bach et al. Dordrecht: Springer, 1995. 59–80. Print. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy 54. DOI: 10.1007/978-94-017-2817-1_4.
  • Borsley, Robert D., Maggie Tallerman, and David Willis. The Syntax of Welsh. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2007. Print.
  • Bresnan, Joan et al. Lexical-Functional Syntax. 2nd ed. Chichester: Wiley Blackwell, 2016. Print. Blackwell Textbooks in Linguistics 16.
  • Butt, Miriam and Tracy Holloway King. “Lexical-Functional Grammar.” Syntax—Theory and Analysis: An International Handbook. Vol. 2. Ed. by Tibor Kiss and Artemis Alexiadou. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton, 2015. 839–74. Handbücher zur Sprach- und Kommunikationswissenschaft 42. Web. 10 Apr. 2015. DOI: 10.1515/9783110363708-002.
  • Carnie, Andrew. Syntax: A Generative Introduction. 3rd ed. Chichester: Wiley Blackwell, 2013. Print. Introducing Linguistics 4.
  • Halpern, Aaron. “Clitics.” The Handbook of Morphology. Ed. by Andrew Spencer and Arnold M. Zwicky. Oxford: Blackwell, 1998. 101–22. Print.
  • Hammarström, Harald et al. “Language: Kwak’wala.” Glottolog. Version 3.0. Max Planck Institute for the Science of Human History, n.d. Web. 10 Apr. 2017. ‹http://glottolog.org/resource/languoid/id/kwak1269›.
  • Klavans, Judith L. “The Independence of Syntax and Phonology in Cliticization.” Language 61.1 (1985): 95–120. Web. 20 Jul. 2016. ‹http://www.jstor.org/stable/413422›.
  • Levine, Robert D. “On the Lexical Origin of the Kwakwala passive.” International Journal of Linguistics 46.4 (1980): 240–59. Web. 10 Apr. 2017. ‹http://www.jstor.org/stable/1264707›.
  • McCloskey, James and Ken Hale. “On the Syntax of Person-Number Inflection in Modern Irish.” Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 1.4 (1984). 487–534. Print. DOI: 10.1007/BF00417057.
  • [Smedt,] Koenraad [de]. “Feature Table.” ParGram/ParSem: An International Collaboration on LFG-Based Grammar and Semantics Development. 2017. U of Bergen, 1 Feb. 2011. Web. 8 Apr. 2017. ‹https://pargram.b.uib.no›.
  • Spencer, Andrew and Ana R. Luís. Clitics: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2012. Print. Cambridge Textbooks in Linguistics.
  • Wälchli, Bernhard. Co-compounds and Natural Coordination. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2005. Print.
  • Zwicky, Arnold M. On Clitics. Bloomington: Indiana U Linguistics Club, 1977. Web. 22 Jul. 2016. ‹https://web.stanford.edu/~zwicky/on_clitics.pdf›.
  • ——— and Geoffrey K. Pullum. “Cliticization vs. Inflection: English N’T.” Language 59.3 (1983): 502–13. Web. 21 Jul. 2016. ‹http://www.jstor.org/stable/413900›.
  1. This list also subsumes the criteria proposed in Zwicky and Pullum (1983), though the page numbers given here refer to Spencer and Luís (2012).
  2. Although this use is probably related to the anaphoric use.
  3. Actually, I’m slightly tempted to make the S a patient here to reflect that the pot does not cause itself to break but rather suffers breaking.
  4. Or, since it’s a fictional language and I’ve never thought about this before, making up supplemental rules.
  5. Honestly, it’s these cases where you wish you could just ask a speaker of your fictional language for their judgement instead of relying on your own intuition, which will most certainly be tainted by interference from your native language. While I am the one to make up the rules for Ayeri, I try to be wary of carrying all too familiar patterns over into my creation accidentally.
  6. The phonology chapter of the new grammar has so far read in a footnote that this would be permissible, though given ku-‘s behavior elsewhere it doesn’t make sense to keep this rule, in retrospect.
  7. Assuming that the person suffix on the verb always co-indexes the topic and that one therefore doesn’t need to distinguish a person-agreement suffix from a homophonous topicalized pronominal suffix is a premature conclusion. In fact, the agreement suffix always agrees with the subject of the verb, which is most often the agent NP but may, in absence of an agent NP, also be the patient NP. The topic may consist of any NP, also oblique ones, which the verb then does not agree in person with.

Interrogatives in Sargaĺk

Sunday, April 16th, 2017
[This post was accidentally deleted, and retrieved from the LCC aggregator]
The interrogatives in Sargaĺk have a few interesting properties, and there are also both gaps and additions in the case system that differ from the case system elsewhere in the language.

Two pronouns correspond to English what: səre and bəre. səre is for count noun-like things, bəre for mass noun-like things. Both lack the pegative form, but səre has several additional locative forms, and the bəre has an ergative form, exceptionally enough. Səre invariantly takes masculine case morphology, even when being a determiner for a feminine noun. Bəre invariantly takes feminine case morphology.

The additional cases for səre are allative -lu, illative -li, elative -rsas.

For persons, the interrogative pronoun is t'əre. T'əre has an accusative form, t'əra. It can take feminine case markers when the answer is assumed or required to be female. The female accusative, t'ərat, is falling out of use in favour of the absolutive. The feminine absolutive is t'əri.

For questions such as 'which X', the pronoun is suffixed to the noun. Otherwise interrogative pronouns are the first element of the NP, or even fronted to sentence-initial position but possibly leaving the NP behind. Usually they are in-situ, though.

A fourth stem with only two forms - the absolutive and the instrumental-comitative - zəre, zərmai. The first is basically a way of asking someone what they think or what they'd say, the second is the main way of asking for a speaker to repeat what he said because you didn't hear. Zərmai is seldom used in any actual phrases, but as a stand-alone word. Essentially zər- sort of is an interrogative for elements of the set of possible utterances.

The interrogative root zər- appears in derived verbs and nouns and adjectives, in ways that parallel the other interrogative pronouns. More about those in a later post.

Detail #337: A System for Encoding Numbers

Thursday, April 13th, 2017
Consider a positional system of numbers based on some form of ordinal thinking. We assume for now a decimal system.

1 is really the first number in the first decad in the first centad in the first millenniad ... ... this means 1 is really ...1111, but we omit leading ones and thus obtain 1. The range ten to nineteen is the second decad. Thus ....11121, ...11122, ...., or as we'd rather have them: 21, 22.

I am not particularly interested in forcing a particular base onto this either, any integer would do... it's just that I want a system where you get the following kind of pattern, given that Z = the base (which also needs a symbol of its own)
1234...Z
21222324...2Z

...
Z1Z2...
211212213214...21Z


We don't need a zero, since we're not interested in those at all: the second '1' may very well come directly after the first '7' for all I am concerned, as long as the pattern is kept intact.

This is fairly similar to bijective numeration in some way, but adds the twist of being slightly off.

Fun thing: there's always an infinite string of 1s to the left of any 'regular' number. One could, however, imagine exceptional numbers where, for instance, there's an infinite string of some other numbers to the left, or an infinite regular pattern (e.g. ...123123123), or even an infinite irregular pattern (reverse your favourite irrational number and drop the decimal mark).

Challenge: develop easy rules for arithmetic for this, without involving conversion back to and from regular numbers.

Language Sketch Needed for Science-Fiction Novel

Thursday, April 13th, 2017

Description

Chris Bronson is looking for a language expert to create a naming language for a science-fiction novel. The language itself is spoken by a group of human beings that have spent the last 80 000 years on another planet, and should therefore be naturalistic yet not obviously related to any existing human language. The employer will share more information with applicants as needed during the solicitation process.
The job itself consists of one basic conlang sketch with romanisation, about 50 words of vocabulary, and rules to create character and location names. Expansion of the original work may be needed in the future, depending on the needs of the employer. Compensation for such additional work will be negotiated separately from the original project.

Employer

Chris Bronson

Application Period

Open until filled

Term

The deadline of the initial project is four months or more after agreement, to be negotiated with the employer.

Compensation

$150 for the project as described above (payment in two $75 instalments at start and conclusion of the project). Additional work to be negotiated with the employer.
Besides compensation, the language creator will be fully credited for their work.

To Apply

Email Chris Bronson at cbrons5988 “at” gmail “dot” com to express your interest in the project. Please include qualifications and samples of previous work.

Note: Please assume that comments left on this post will not be read by the employer.

#496

Saturday, April 8th, 2017

While we know little about actual Gallifreyan, we could guess that Time Lords’ sentences are based on Regenerative Grammar.

Conlanger Lore: Reasoning about Grammar

Saturday, April 8th, 2017
In part, this intermittent series of posts will deal with reasoning and knowledge in linguistics, when applied in such an unusual way as conlanging is.

One notion that forms part of the backbone of conlanging thought is the idea that we can just apply reasoning at a very basic level to reach conclusions about typology.

Consider, for instance, pro-drop. Common wisdom is that pro-drop and verbal marking for subjects (and possibly objects) go together. Superficially, this seems reasonable, but we know there are languages that have subject congruence, but do not permit pro-drop. Likewise, we know there are languages that have pro-drop, but don't mark their verbs.


Common wisdom is that lack of case (and/or verbal marking) forces word order to be fixed. But many languages without case marking permit some amount of word order rearrangement - Swedish, for instance, permits both SVO and OVS, without any explicit marking. This to the extent that I have been in situations where people have parsed what I have said (SVO) as OVS, because they have parsed contextual cues and salient features of the words involved in the utterances differently than I would have expected.

Yes, of course Swedish doesn't have strictly free word order - SVO still probably accounts for at least nearly the majority of utterances, followed by AVSO (where A = adverbial), followed by some oddities like VO (with omitted subject), followed by OVS fairly far down the line. The point is, you don't need the case marking to free the word order, what you need it for is to obtain very free word order, that is, word order where the different orders don't significantly differ statistically, and thus make it hard even to learn what is what. 

The point I am trying to reach is that ultimately, we cannot rely on ideas like "IFF X is marked in one way, then X can be left unmarked in other ways". Some languages simply structure their utterances in ways where who or what the subject is is irrelevant. In some languages, discourse tends to focus more on events than on people involved, in some languages the discourse is more interested in the who does what aspect of it. Much like some languages don't have tense. Further, with subjects and objects, oftentimes there is a significant bunch of additional knowledge the speaker and listener can be assumed to share, and this makes looking at whether the subject can be retrieved from other markings with regards to pro-drop, or whether the subject can be resolved from other markings with regards to case.

Thus, when we reason about language, we need to acknowledge that the actual form is not IFF X, then Y, but rather if any X out of a huge bunch of unknowns, then maybe Y.

Detail #336: Modelling Restrictions on Compounds

Thursday, April 6th, 2017
Languages with compounds can have restrictions on what compounds are permitted. Describing such a system of restrictions in some depth could be a nice way of getting an impressive grammar done. Let us consider some ways of 'modelling' such a system. There's a difference between modelling and exhaustively describing, in some sense.

Giving an exhaustive description is possible for a conlanger: we inform the reader how it works and since we're the creators, our fiat holds. However, this might be somewhat uninteresting. Models are interesting in that they attempt to catch what happens, but might simplify some stuff and therefore be mistaken about things as well.

Given the natural scope of a language - spoken over generations, spoken by lots of speakers in varying relations with one another (all the way from family to have never ever interacted due to not even living in the same centuries nor even geographically all that close) it is likely for there to be a lot of variation in some parts of the language, and thus a model makes a lot of sense: it'll be wrong some of the time, but it'll catch the main traits of the system.

So, let's consider compounding and how we could model restrictions on it. First, we can recognize two types of edges of a compound: the left edge and the right edge. We can imagine a compound that does not permit any added morpheme to the left, and the same goes for the right. We call these 'right-saturated' and 'left-saturated' compounds. A compound that is saturated at both edges is simply saturated.

Another thing about modelling is that it'd be good if it also helped parse the compounds. Thus, a good model should tell us whether an element in a compound is a left-branch or a right-branch by looking at the word. It should even, probably, tell us whether two neighbouring elements are only "superficial" neighbours.
Left and right-branching

This gives our model some actual usefulness beyond its 'descriptive' power. Now we come to the nitty-gritty stuff. We of course want to have some way of quantifying whether a word accepts compounding. Let's simply use numbers for this - we could put it in a range [0, 1], where 1 is 'accepts compounding' and '0' is 'saturated' and values inbetween are probabilistic estimates as to how likely it is to accept compounding. So, we have, for any word, two values left and right ∈ [0, 1]. I'll write left and right as a single vector C = (x, y), where x is the left and y is the right edge. Subscript text comes in four varieties: full words represent themselves. Thus CDonauSchiff is the compound of Donau and Schiff. One-letter capital variables represent an arbitrary word. Small letters

Let us take two words, Donau and Schiff. These have associated vectors CDonau and CSchiff. The resulting Donauschiff too has the associated vector CDonauSchiff, which is a product of the vectors of the two elements. The interesting thing, of course, is the function that takes  CDonau and CSchiff and produces CDonauSchiff. It should be clear that order is relevant - we wouldn't expect Schiffdonau and Donauschiff to have the same properties. A very simple model would do something like this:
CEF = (El, Fr), where l and r as subscripts mark "left edge value" and "right edge value".
In such a model, the property at the edges carry on down. However, there's no a priori reason why ABl = Al and ABr = Br. In other words, there's no reason why a compound's edges should have the same compounding-properties as the element that occupies those edges - shoemaker needs not have the same left-edge property as shoe and right-edge property as maker - in fact, we'd sort of maybe expect, in English, that shoemaker would be more similar at the left edge to maker than to shoe (but not maybe entirely so). The compound is a new word, possibly a word of a different word-class (with regards to at least one of its parts), and thus it seems unjustified to expect the compoundability to be conserved at edges.

Thus we probably want a more detailed idea of what compounds are permitted - we might want both Cl and Cr to be vectors for different types of lexemes: verbs, proper nouns, nouns of different classes, adjectives of different kinds, etc. We might even want to go further: probabilities for specific inflected forms, probabilities for 'heavy' words vs. 'light' words, measured by their nested structure, etc.

Amyways, my next step in modelling this would be to come up with some kind of 'average' probability per word class pair, e.g. adjective-noun 75%, inanimate_noun-transitive_verb 80%. Once this is done, I'd make a weighted graph, where nodes are types of words, and directed edges are the probability of a word of one type compounding before a word of some other type. Self-cycles may exist.

Next, each lexical item in the conlang's lexicon would be given a run where a randomizer decides whether it'll accept a certain word-type as prefix or suffix with the probability given by that graph. The probabilities for the new word's edges would be based on some way of measuring 'saturation', which again creates a new thing we might need: a saturated word does not permit more suffixes, and this may happen even if there are non-zero probabilities going on for some level of the compound at the edges.

I am not going to present any algorithm for this now, this is basically an early rambling intended to come up with something.