For the past months, work on writing my grammar has been stalling since I’ve been trying to figure out which of the functional morphemes that are maybe a little untypical as inflections might in fact be clitics. After having read Spencer and LuÃs (2012) on the topic nearly cover-to-cover, I’ve become a little disenchanted about the whole effort, since clitics appear to be very elusive things which can’t be easily defined in a formal way (126). Based on my reading, some characteristic traits appear to be:
- Clitics behave in part like function words and in part like affixes, but in any case they are not free morphemes (38, 42).
- Clitics tend to be phonologically weak items (39).
- Clitics prominently—and importantly—tend to attach ‘promiscuously’ to surrounding words. That is, unlike inflection, they are not limited to connect to a certain part of speech or to align with their host in semantics (40, 108–109).
- Clitics tend to appear in a second position, whether that is after a word or an intonational or syntactic phrase (41)
- Clitics tend to be templatic and to cluster, especially if they encode inflection-like information (41, 47–48).
- Clitics have none of the freedom of ordering found in true words and phrases (43).
- Positions of ‘special’ clitics tend to not be available to free words (44).
- Clitics tend to be functional morphemes, and to realize a single morphosyntactic property (67, 179).
- There are no paradigmatic gaps (108–109).
- There tends to be no morphophonemic alteration like vowel harmony, stress shift or sandhi between a clitic and its host (108–109).
- There tends to be no idiosyncratic change in meaning when a clitic and a clitic host come together, unlike there may be with inflection (108, 110).
- Similar to affixes, clitics and their host tend to be treated as a syntactic unit, that is, there is lexical integrity, so you can’t put word material in between a clitic and its host (108, 110).
- Clitics usually get joined to a host word after inflection (108, 110)
- Affixes tend to go on every word in a conjunct (narrow scope), while clitics have a tendency to treat a conjunct as a unit to attach to (wide scope; 139, 196 ff.).
However, Spencer and LuÃs (2012) point out many counterexamples in order to drive their point home that the border between clitics and affixes is often fuzzy. It comes as no surprise that according to their assessment, there’s a lot of miscategorization in individual grammars as a result (107). Another consequence of definitional fuzziness is that since not all of the traits described above are always present, making a checklist and summing up the tally is only of limited value. The traits enumerated above are sufficient, but not necessary, conditions.
This blog article has become rather long and technical in retrospect, but I needed to write it all down in order to get a clear head about the status of various particles and affixes in Ayeri which behave not quite like function words or inflection, and which I’ve thus long suspected to belong to the interstitial category of clitics. The first part of this article will detail all the particles and affixes which precede the lexical heads they modify, the second one will elaborate on suffixes. This article is also likely to find its way into the 2016/17 edition of the Ayeri Grammar, which I’m still working on, as a subchapter to the chapter on morphological typology.
1. Preposed particles and prefixes
Now, I think what should be rather unproblematic with regards to analysis as clitics in Ayeri are the preverbal elements, that is, the topic marker, one or several modal particles, the progressive marker, and also the emphatic affirmative and negative discourse particles. All of these particles essentially have functional rather than lexical content, and are usually unstressed. They come in a cluster with a fixed order, and they appear in a position where no ordinary word material could go, since Ayeri is strictly verb-initial. In conjuncts it’s also unnecessary to mark every verb with one or several of them:
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- kece
- ket-ye
- wash-3SG.F
- nay
- nay
- and
- dayungisaye
- dayungisa-ye
- dress-3SG.F
- mÄva
- mÄva-Ø
- mother-TOP
- yanjas
- yan-ye-as
- boy-PL-P
- yena.
- yena
- 3SG.F.GEN
‘The mother washes and dresses her boys.’
- Manga
- manga
- PROG
- sahaya
- saha-ya
- come-3SG.M
- rangya
- rang-ya
- home-LOC
- nay
- nay
- and
- nedraya
- nedra-ya
- sit-3SGM
- ang
- ang
- A
- Tikim.
- Tikim
- Tikim
‘Tikim is coming home and sitting down.’
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- mya
- mya
- be.supposed.to
- ming
- ming
- can
- sidegongya
- sideg-ong-ya.Ø
- repair-IRR-3SG.M.TOP
- nay
- nay
- and
- la-lataya
- la~lata-ya.Ø
- ITER~sell-3SG.M.TOP
- ajamyeley.
- ajam-ye-ley
- toy-PL-P.INAN
‘He should be able to repair and resell the toys.’
In (1a), therefore, the agent-topic marker ang only occurs before kece ‘(she) washes’, and the conjoined verb dayungisaye ‘(she) dresses’ is also within its scope. Repeating the marker as well before the latter verb could either be considered ungrammatical because there is only one topic there—mÄva ‘mother’—or the sentence could be interpreted as having two conjoined clauses with different subjects: ‘She1 washes and mother2 dresses her boys.’ The latter outcome has mÄva as the topic only of dayungisaye, while kece‘s topic is the person marking on the verb—a pro-drop subject, essentially.
In (1b), then, the progressive marker manga equally has scope over both verb conjuncts, sahaya ‘(he) comes’ and nedraya ‘(he) sits’ in what I presume is a case of extended/distributed exponence, since the verb conjuncts can be represented by the incomplete f-structure matrix (cf. Bresnan et al. 2016; Butt and King 2015) shown in (2). Manga is treated there as being part of things the verb inflects for, that is, progressive aspect. The topic marker ang is not a semantic property of the verb, but announces the case and—for agents and patients—the animacy value of the topicalized noun phrases (NPs), so the f-structure in (2) lists this information under the TOP relation.
-
Part of the f-structure of saha- ‘come’ in (1b):
PRED |
‘come ⟨(↑ SUBJ), (↑ OBLloc)⟩’ |
ASP |
PROG |
TOP |
|
… |
Modal particles, exemplified in (1c), are probably slightly less typical as clitics since it seems feasible for them to be stressed for contrast. What is not possible, however, is to front either mya or ming, and the verb itself also can’t precede the particles, which is demonstrated in (3). It’s also not possible to coordinate any of the elements in the preverbal particle cluster with nay ‘and’, as we will see in (4).
-
- * mya ang ming sidegongya
- * ming ang mya sidegongya
- * sidegongya ang mya ming
-
- * ang nay mya ming sidegongya
- * ang mya nay ming sidegongya
- * ang mya ming nay sidegongya
It needs to be pointed out that unlike verbs, modal particles in Ayeri resist inflection, so in (1c) the irrealis suffix -ong is realized on the verb sidegongya ‘(he) would repair’ instead of on one or both of the modal particles as * mingong and * myong, respectively. The combination of mya ‘be supposed to’ with an irrealis-marked verb together indicates that the speaker thinks the action denoted by the verb should be carried out. On the other hand, the marking on the verb may also be interpreted as being valid for the whole verb complex, and just generally adds the feature [MOOD IRR] to the verb’s feature list in analogy to [ASP PROG] in (2). With regards to negation, it’s just the same: only the verb can be negated, but not the modal particle. Possibly, it would be useful in this case to abstract the modal particles as a feature [MODALITY] as listed by ParGram for purposes of functional representation. At least superficially, it looks as though Ayeri acts differently from English here in that the verb is possibly not a complement of the modal. I suppose that this is mostly apparent from the fact that in Ayeri, the verb inflects, not the modal particle. Furthermore, modal particles in Ayeri can’t be modified by adverbs like regular verbs can:
-
- Ming
- ming
- can
- tigalye
- tigal-ye
- swim-3SG.F
- ban
- ban
- well
- nilay
- nilay
- probably
- ang
- ang
- A
- Diya.
- Diya
- Diya
‘Diya can probably swim well.’
- * 
- Ming
- ming
- can
- nilay
- nilay
- probably
- tigalye
- tigal-ye
- swim-3SG.F
- ban
- ban
- well
- ang
- ang
- A
- Diya.
- Diya
- Diya
In order to not confuse things even more, it seems advisable to decree that combinations of topic particle and modal particle, as well as modal particle and verb, likewise not be interrupted by parenthetical material like naratang ‘they say’, so that:
-
- * 
- ​​Naratang,​​
- nara-tang
- say-3PL.M.A
- ang
- ang
- AT
- ming
- ming
- can
- tigalye
- tigal-ye
- swim-3SG.F
- ban
- ban
- well
- Diya
- Diya
- Diya
- kodanya.
- kodan-ya
- lake-LOC
‘They say Diya can swim well in a lake.’
- * Ang, naratang, ming tigalye ban Diya kodanya.
- * Ang ming, naratang, tigalye ban Diya kodanya.
- ? Ang ming tigalye, naratang, ban Diya kodanya.
- Ang ming tigalye ban, naratang, Diya kodanya.
- Ang ming tigalye ban Diya, naratang, kodanya.
- Ang ming tigalye ban Diya kodanya, naratang.
Of all the other parts of speech, only nouns also have preposed modifiers. This is the case with proper nouns, where the name will be preceded by a case marker instead of receiving a case-marking suffix. This case marker is phonologically weak in that it is no longer than other affixes, and unstressed, with the exception of the causative case marker sÄ, which bears at least secondary stress since it contains a long vowel. We already saw case particles preceding names in (1b) and (5) above: ang Tikim and ang Diya; ang marks the proper-noun NPs as agents in both cases. The case marker is missing when the NP is topicalized, as exemplified by (6), where the agent NP appears as just Diya, not ang Diya. While case suffixes have narrow scope as in (7a) and thus need to be repeated on every NP in a conjunct, preposed case markers may be used with wide scope if both conjuncts are proper nouns as in (7c). Narrow scope with proper nouns may add an individuating connotation in (7d).
-
- Toryon
- tor-yon
- sleep-3PL.N
- veneyang
- veney-ang
- dog-A
- nay
- nay
- and
- badanang.
- badan-ang
- father-A
‘The dog and father are (both) sleeping.’
- * 
- Toryon
- tor-yon
- sleep-3PL.N
- veney
- veney_
- dog_
- nay
- nay
- and
- badanang.
- badan-ang
- father-A
- Sa
- sa
- PT
- sobisayan
- sobisa-yan
- study-3PL.M
- ang
- ang
- A
- Niva
- Niva
- Niva
- nay
- nay
- and
- Mico
- Mico
- Mico
- narÄnye.
- narÄn-ye-Ø
- language-PL-TOP
‘Languages is what Niva and Mico study.’
- Sa
- sa
- PT
- sobisayan
- sobisa-yan
- study-3PL.M
- ang
- ang
- A
- Niva
- Niva
- Niva
- nay
- nay
- and
- ang
- ang
- A
- Mico
- Mico
- Mico
- narÄnye.
- narÄn-ye-Ø
- language-PL-TOP
‘Languages is what Niva and Mico (each) study.’
Taking the above characteristics into account, one may argue that the preposed case markers are clitics. They also often enough follow other phonetic material, so it should be possible to analyze case markers as indiscriminately attaching to the word on the left while syntactically modifying the word to the right:
- ? Sa sobisayan=ang Niva nay Mico narÄnye.
There is no audible break or change in intonation between sobisayan and ang, and there is also no morphophonemic modification occurring between them either: if ang were a suffix, stress would shift from /sobiˈsajan/ to /sobiËŒsajaˈnang/. According to Klavans (1985), a clitic’s phonological leaning to the preceding word while modifying the following one is a process which is attested in natural languages, and she quotes examples from Kwak’wala, a Wakashan language of British Columbia (Hammarström et al. 2017), for instance:
- Adapted from Klavans (1985: 106):
[Kwak’wala]
- nəp’idi-da
- throw-DEIC
- gənanəm
- child
- [x̣a
- OBJ
- gukÊ·]​​​N​’​​
- house
- [sa
- OBL
- t’isÉ™m]​​​N​’​​
- rock
‘The child hit the house with a rock by throwing.’ (Levine 1980)

Since clitics should be treated as syntactically coherent with their hosts, it shouldn’t be possible, then, to interrupt sobisayan and ang with parenthetical word material in the same way it wasn’t possible in (6). This assumption proves false, however, since Ayeri does not take an issue with placing things other than a case marker after the verb cluster and before the first NP, while the interruption of ang and Niva, on the other hand, is indeed ungrammatical:
-
- Sa
- sa
- PT
- sobisayan,
- sobisa-yan
- study-3PL.M
- naratang,
- nara-tang
- say-3PL.M.A
- ang
- ang
- A
- Niva
- Niva
- Niva
- nay
- nay
- and
- Mico
- Mico
- Mico
- narÄnye.
- narÄn-ye-Ø
- language-PL-TOP
‘Languages is what Niva and Mico, they say, study.’
- * 
- Sa
- sa
- PT
- sobisayan
- sobisa-yan
- study-3PL.M
- ang,
- ang
- A
- naratang,
- nara-tang
- say-3PL.M.A
- Niva
- Niva
- Niva
- nay
- nay
- and
- Mico
- Mico
- Mico
- narÄnye.
- narÄn-ye-Ø
- language-PL-TOP
It is furthermore possible for the case marker to begin an utterance, namely, in equative sentences like the one in (11a). In this case, there is no way for the case marker to lean on a host to its left, but only to its right. In these cases as well, it isn’t possible for parenthetical material to be placed between the case marker and its target of modification, as in (11b).
-
-
- Ang
- ang
- A
- Misan
- Misan
- Misan
- lajÄyas
- lajÄy-as
- student-P
- puti.
- puti
- zealous
‘Misan is a zealous student.’
-
* 
- Ang,
- ang
- A
- paronyang,
- paron-yang
- believe-1SG.A
- Misan
- Misan
- Misan
- lajÄyas
- lajÄy-as
- student-P
- puti.
- puti
- zealous
Since the case marker and its modification target cohere that closely, we have to assume that here as well, the case marker is proclitic rather than enclitic. Unlike “typical” clitics, however, its attachment is not strictly speaking ‘promiscuous’, unlike in our first hypothesis, but always with a proper noun very specifically. This property puts it very close to an affix—just like the suffixed case markers. More typical of function words, though, there is no morphophonemic interaction between the flexive and the word it inflects, for example, there is no /saËdÊ’aËn/ from sa (P) + AjÄn. This overlap in form between affix and function word is typical of clitics, according to the traits excerpted from Spencer and LuÃs (2012) above, and what Klavans (1985) characterizes as “double citizenship”. Moreover, sÄ, as mentioned above, represents an exception to other case particles in that it takes secondary stress due to being a long syllable, which cannot be unstressed. Ayeri does not allow words to end in secondary-stressed syllables, but only allows secondary-stressed syllables to precede a stressed one, since word stress spreads backwards from the right edge of phonological words. If we don’t want to create an exception for sÄ alone, thus, it is more likely for the preposed case markers to lean to the right rather than to the left also on phonological grounds, like in (12).
- Sa sobisayan ang=Niva nay Mico narÄnye.
From this discussion of prenominal particles, let us return to verbs again for a moment. Besides the preverbal particles discussed above, there is also what is spelled as a prefix on the verb which appears to be a little odd as such in that it can have wide scope over conjoined verbs. This is the prefix da- often meaning ‘so, thus’, displayed in (13).
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- da-pinyaya
- da-pinya-ya
- so-ask-3SG.M
- nay
- nay
- and
- hisaya
- hisa-ya
- beg-3SG.M
-
- Ø
- TOP
- Yan
- Yan
- Yan
- sa
- sa
- P
- Pila.
- Pila
- Pila
‘Yan asks and begs Pila to (do so).’
Da-, where it is not used for presentative purposes, is a functional morpheme in that it basically acts as an anaphora for a complementizer phrase (CP) the speaker chooses to drop. Thus, it does not mark any of the intrinsic morphological categories of the verb (tense, aspect, mood, modality, finiteness), just like the topic marker refers to a syntactic relation the verb subcategorizes but none of its inflectional categories. As an anaphora, da- cannot stand alone, though it is possible to use a full demonstrative form danya ‘such one’ in its place:
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- da-pinyaya
- da-pinya-ya
- so-ask-3SG.M
- nay
- nay
- and
- hisaya
- hisa-ya
- beg-3SG.M
-
- Ø
- TOP
- Yan
- Yan
- Yan
- sa
- sa
- P
- Pila
- Pila
- Pila
- danyaley.
- danya-ley
- such.one-P.INAN
‘Yan asks and begs Pila such.’
Unlike the preverbal clitics, da- can be associated with a full form, though it still displays special syntax in that unlike English -n’t or ‘ll, for instance, it does not occur in the same place as the full form. Note also how da- is appended to the right of tense prefixes, which express a property of the verb, as shown in (15).
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- da-məpinyaya
- da-mə-pinya-ya.Ø
- so-PST-ask-3SG.M.TOP
- sa
- sa
- P
- Pila.
- Pila
- Pila
‘He asked Pila to.’
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- da-məpinyaya
- da-mə-pinya-ya.Ø
- so-PST-ask-3SG.M
- nay
- nay
- and
- məhisaya
- mə-hisa-ya.Ø
- PST-beg-3SG.M
- sa
- sa
- TOP
- Pila.
- Pila
- Yan
‘Yan asked and begged Pila to.’
The verb from in (15) becomes ungrammatical with the order of its prefixes reversed, so it is not acceptable to say: * məda-pinyaya, although note that pre- and suffixes proper also have a fixed order in Ayeri, so this alone is not enough evidence to claim that da- is not possibly a prefix. Furthermore, while the tense prefixes undergo crasis, this is not the case with da-:
-
- Da-amangreng.
- da-amang-reng
- thus-happen-3SG.INAN.A
‘It happens thus.’
- * DÄmangreng.
-
- MÄmangreng.
- mÉ™-amang-reng
- PST-happen-3SG.INAN.A
‘It happened.’
- * Məamangreng.
Besides the characteristic of not seeking out certain parts of speech, the da- prefix at least satisfies the criteria of being a phonologically reduced form of an otherwise free functional morpheme, and it occurs in a place where normal syntax would not put its corresponding full form. It has wide scope over conjuncts, is attached outside of inflection for proper categories of the verb, and doesn’t interact with its host with regards to morphophonemics. Besides these more typical traits of clitics, there is also no way to place words between da- and the verb stem:
- *
- Da,
- da
- thus
- naratang,
- nara-tang
- say-3PL.M.A
- amangreng.
- amang-reng
- happen-3SG.INAN.A
Intended: ‘It happens, they say, thus.’
The prefix sitang- ‘self’ behaves in the same way as da-, since it also abbreviates a reflexive NP, for instance, sitang-yes ‘herself’ where ‘herself’ as a patient is coreferential with the agent of the clause. Reflexivity, however, is a category a verb in Ayeri could be said to inflect for that way, though Ayeri also does not have any verbs which are obligatorily reflexive to indicate anticausativity like in Romance languages:
-
- Adruara
- adru-ara
- break-3SG.INAN
- biratayreng.
- biratay-reng
- pot-A.INAN
‘The pot broke.’
- * 
- Sitang-adruara
- sitang-adru-ara
- self-break-3SG.INAN
- biratayreng.
- biratay-reng
- pot-A.INAN
-
[French]
- Le
- le
- the
- pot
- pot
- pot
- s’est
- se=est
- self=be.3SG.PRES
- cassé.
- cassé
- broken
‘The pot broke.’ (an unspecified force broke it)
- Le
- le
- the
- pot
- pot
- pot
- est
- est
- be.3SG.PRES
- cassé.
- cassé
- broken
‘The pot is broken.’
Ayeri has a tendency to reuse prefixes with different parts of speech, and thus da- is also used with nouns, forming part of the series of deictic prefixes, da- ‘such (a)’, eda- ‘this’, ada- ‘that’. The prefix in all these cases represents a grammatical function, is unstressed, and may have wide scope over conjoined NPs, unless an individuating interpretation is intended, as in (21b). These traits are typical of clitics, as we have seen, though (22) shows that unlike with verbs, the deictic prefixes do undergo crasis here, which is a trait more typically associated with affixes.
-
- SinyÄng
- sinya-ang
- who-A
- eda-ledanas
- eda-ledan-as
- this-friend-P
- nay
- nay
- and
- viretÄyÄs
- viretÄya-as
- supporter-P
- tondayena-hen?
- tonday-ena-hen
- art-GEN-all
‘Who is this friend and supporter of all arts?’
- SinyÄng
- sinya-ang
- who-A
- eda-ledanas
- eda-ledan-as
- this-friend-P
- nay
- nay
- and
- eda-viretÄyÄs
- eda-viretÄya-as
- this-supporter-P
- tondayena-hen?
- tonday-ena-hen
- art-GEN-all
‘Who is/are this friend and this supporter of all arts?’
-
- Sa
- sa
- PT
- ming
- ming
- can
- nelnang
- nel-nang
- help-1PL.A
- edÄyon.
- eda-ayon-Ø
- this-man-TOP
‘This man, we can help him.’
The deictic prefixes also cannot be used with all types of NPs, only with those headed by generic and proper nouns; the picky nature of the deictic prefixes also makes them more typical of affixes than of clitics. The preverbal particles, on the other hand, also only occur with verbs, and I’ve nonetheless argued for them being clitics above.
As mentioned initially, Spencer and LuÃs (2012) give numerous counterexamples to the catalog of traits typically associated with clitics. One of this counterexample is what they term ‘suspended affixation’, which occurs in Turkish, for instance, where the plural suffix -lEr and subsequent suffixes can be left out in coordination (23a), as well as case markers (23b), and adverbials with case-like functions (23c):
-
-
[Turkish]
- bütün
- all
- kitap(…)
- book
- ve
- and
- defter-ler-imiz
- notebook-PL-1PL.POSS
‘all our books and notebooks’ (199)
-
- Vapur
- boat
- hem
- and
- Napoli(…)
- Naples
- hem
- and
- Venedik’-e
- Venice-LOC
- uÄŸruyormuÅŸ
- stops.EVIDENTIAL
‘Apparently the boat stops at both Naples and Venice’ (ibid.)
-
- öğretmen-ler(…)
- teacher-PL
- ve
- and
- öğrenci-ler-le
- student-PL-WITH
‘with (the) students and (the) teachers’ (ibid.)
They note that, in “the nominal domain especially, wide scope inflection is widespread in the languages of Eurasia, becoming more prominent from west to east”, and that wide scope affixation “can be found with inflectional and derivational morphology in a number of languages, and it is often a symptom of recent and not quite complete morphologization” (200). They report Wälchli (2005) to find that this is especially the case with ‘natural coordination’, that is, the combination of items very frequently occurring in pairs like knife and fork or mother and father, as opposed to cases of occasional coordination (Spencer and LuÃs 2012: 200). Whether this is also true for Ayeri would require a separate survey.
Given the evidence from Turkish, the categorization of deictic prefixes as either affixes or clitics is unclear, especially since the diagnostic of scope is devalued by the Turkish examples. On the other hand, suffixes on nouns don’t behave this way, as demonstrated in (24)—they rather behave like typical affixes in that they mandatorily occur on each conjunct. The question is, thus, whether an exception should be made for prefixes on nouns. We may as well assume that they are clitics.
-
- sobayajang
- sobaya-ye-ang
- teacher-PL-A
- nay
- nay
- and
- lajÄyjang
- lajÄy-ye-ang
- student-PL-A
‘(the) teachers and (the) students’
- * 
- sobayaye
- sobaya-ye
- teacher-PL
- nay
- nay
- and
- lajÄyjang
- lajÄy-ye-ang
- student-PL-A
- * 
- sobaya
- sobaya
- teacher
- nay
- nay
- and
- lajÄyjang
- lajÄy-ye-ang
- student-PL-A
From a functional point of view, the exact nature of the deictic prefixes shouldn’t matter either way—ParGram also cites a [DEIXIS] feature with PROXIMAL and DISTAL as its values, which fits eda- ‘this’ and ada- ‘that’ just fine. At present I’m at a loss about the feature representation of ‘such (a)’, however, since it is clearly deictic, but neither proximal nor distal. In this case it should be possible to just use [DEIXIS this/that/such] as well, I suppose, hence:
-
-
- edÄyon
- eda-ayon
- this-man
‘this man’
-
As described above, proper nouns are case marked by probably clitic case markers in front of the noun. In fact, these markers are somewhere at the left periphery of the NP, so the deictic prefixes stand in between the case marker and the proper noun itself, which is unproblematic for lexical integrity, since the deictic prefixes are not free morphemes. And even if they were part of inflection, the case markers, as clitics, would be on the outside—the order deictic prefix – case marker – noun is ungrammatical. An example is given in (26).
-
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- koronay
- koron-ay.Ø
- know-1SG.TOP
- sa
- sa
- P
- eda-​kagan.
- eda-​kagan
- this-Kagan
‘I know this Kagan.’
-
* 
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- koronay
- koron-ay.Ø
- know-1SG.TOP
- eda-​kaganas.
- eda-​kagan-as
- this-Kagan-P
-
* 
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- koronay
- koron-ay.Ø
- know-1SG.TOP
- eda-sa
- eda-sa
- this-P
- Kagan.
- Kagan
- Kagan
The question now is, what happens to coordinated proper nouns? Since the suffixed case markers on common nouns have the distributional properties of affixes, they occur on every conjunct, the deictic prefix, however, only occurs on the first unless an individuating reading is intended, as shown in (20). For proper nouns it ought to be possible for both a case marker and a deictic prefix to have scope over coordinated proper nouns (27a). Yet, however, my gut tells me that this is slightly odd-sounding (German/English bias?), so I would prefer the strategy in (27b), which avoids the problem altogether by making the names an adjunct to the demonstrative edanya ‘this/these one(s)’. The example in (27c) is unproblematic and here as well indicates that the two people are referred to individually and not as a group.
-
-
? 
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- koronay
- koron-ay.Ø
- know-1SG.TOP
- sa
- sa
- P
- eda-​Kagan
- eda-​Kagan
- this-​Kagan
- nay
- nay
- and
- IjÄn.
- IjÄn
- IjÄn
‘I know these Kagan and IjÄn.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- koronay
- koron-ay.Ø
- know-1SG.TOP
- edanyÄs,
- edanya-as
- this.one-P
- Kagan
- Kagan
- Kagan
- nay
- nay
- and
- IjÄn.
- IjÄn
- IjÄn
‘I know these, Kagan and IjÄn.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- koronay
- koron-ay.Ø
- know-1SG.TOP
- sa
- sa
- P
- eda-​Kagan
- eda-​Kagan
- this-​Kagan
- nay
- nay
- and
- eda-​IjÄn.
- eda-​IjÄn
- this-​IjÄn
‘I know this Kagan and this IjÄn.’
Of the deictic prefixes, da- is not only available to verbs and nouns, but also to adjectives. Like with verbs, it is short for danya ‘such one’ in this case (28a). The resulting meaning is ‘the adj. one’; da- essentially acts as a nominalizer, at least to the extent the compound of da- + adjective inherits the distributional properties of danya as a demonstrative pronoun. Thus, it can be case- and topic marked (28bc), and also be modified by another adjective (28c). On the other hand, it can’t be reduplicated for diminution, and also also can’t be pluralized. Since adjectives follow their heads, the original order of demonstrative – adjective remains intact.
-
-
- Le
- le
- PT.INAN
- noyang
- no-yang
- want-1SG.A
- danyaley
- danya-Ø
- such.one-TOP
- tuvo.
- tuvo
- red
‘The red one I want.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- noay
- no-ay.Ø
- want-1SG.TOP
- da-tuvoley.
- da-tuvo-ley
- one-red-P.INAN
‘I want the red one.’
-
- Le
- le
- PT.INAN
- noyang
- no-yang
- want-1SG.A
- da-tuvo
- da-tuvo-Ø
- small
- kivo.
- kivo
‘The little red one I want.’
The prefix, again, coheres tightly in that no additional material can be inserted. Like with nouns above, inflecting each form in a group of coordinated adjectives results in an individuating reading (29a). It should be possible for the prefix to take wide scope (29b), though it seems better to me to instead rephrase the coordinated adjective as a relative clause (28c), for instance, besides using the full form danya + adjectives. Since case markers go on every conjunct, (29d) is not grammatical.
-
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- noay
- no-ay.Ø
- want-1SG.TOP
- da-tuvoley
- da-tuvo-ley
- one-red-P.INAN
- nay
- nay
- and
- da-lenoley.
- da-leno-ley
- one-blue-P.INAN
‘I want the blue one and the red one.’
-
? 
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- noay
- no-ay.Ø
- want-1SG.TOP
- da-tuvoley
- da-tuvo-ley
- one-red-P.INAN
- nay
- nay
- and
- lenoley.
- leno-ley
- blue-P.INAN
‘I want the red and blue one.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- noay
- no-ay.Ø
- want-1SG.TOP
- adaley
- ada-ley
- that-P.INAN
- si
- si
- REL
- tuvo
- tuvo
- red
- nay
- nay
- and
- leno.
- leno
- blue
‘I want that which is red and blue.’
-
* 
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- noay
- no-ay.Ø
- want-1SG.TOP
- da-tuvo
- da-tuvo
- one-red
- nay
- nay
- and
- lenoley.
- leno-ley
- blue-P.INAN
Possessive pronouns like nÄ ‘my’, vana ‘your’, etc. behave the same way when derived to free-standing anaphora (da-nÄ ‘mine’, da-vana ‘yours’, etc.) from their usual role as modifiers, except they can’t themselves be modified by adjectives in the way da-tuvo ‘the red one’ is in (28c). Taking all of the examples above into account, da- with adjectives and possessive pronouns seems to be most like a simple clitic according to Zwicky’s (1977) definition, compared to the other contexts it can appear in:
Cases where a free morpheme, when unaccented, may be phonologically subordinated to a neighboring word. Cliticization of this sort is usually associated with stylistic conditions, as in the casual speech cliticization of object pronouns in English; there are both formal full pronouns and casual reduced pronouns. (Zwicky 1977: 5)
Typical of a simple clitic as well, the distribution of da- is restricted by grammatical context, as pointed out regarding example (27b). Unlike in English, which Zwicky (1977) gives examples of, the condition in Ayeri is likely not phonological in this case. The nature of the condition, however, is not predetermined in Spencer and LuÃs (2012), when they write that
we may therefore need to define simple clitics along the lines of Halpern (1998), namely, as clitics that may be positioned in a subset of the positions within which the full forms are found, rather than as clitics that have the same distribution as their full-form counterparts as in Zwicky (1977). Under this broader definition, we capture the fact that simple clitics differ from special clitics in that they can appear in some of the positions that are occupied by their corresponding full forms, while special clitics never can. (Spencer and LuÃs 2012: 44)
Besides deictic prefixes, nouns may also receive a prefix expressing likeness, ku-. This prefix is also applicable to adjectives, and is maybe more adverbial in terms of semantics than purely functional morphemes like da-. In contrast to da-, ku- has no full-form equivalent. Some examples of it leaning on nouns are given in (30). Like the deictic prefixes, ku- appears in a position which is privileged to dependent functional morphemes in that any modifiers which appear as free words or phrases (adjectives, relative clauses, nominal adjuncts) follow nouns. Slightly untypical of a clitic, it is not fully ‘promiscuous’ regarding its phonological host in that it requires a nominal, adjectival or phrasal host.
-
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- misya
- mis-ya
- act-3SG.M
-
- Ø
- TOP
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- ku-depangas.
- ku-depang-as
- like-fool-P
‘AmÄn acts like a fool.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- misya
- mis-ya
- act-3SG.M
-
- Ø
- TOP
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- ku-depangas
- ku-depang-as
- like-fool-P
- nay
- nay
- and
- karayÄs.
- karaya-as
- coward-P
‘AmÄn acts like a fool and a coward.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- misya
- mis-ya
- act-3SG.M
-
- Ø
- TOP
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- ku-depangas
- ku-depang-as
- like-fool-P
- nay
- nay
- and
- ku-karayÄs.
- ku-karaya-as
- ku-coward-P
‘AmÄn acts like a fool and like a coward.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- misya
- mis-ya
- act-3SG.M
-
- Ø
- TOP
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- ku-ada-depangas.
- ku-ada-depang-as
- like-that-fool-P
‘AmÄn acts like that fool.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- misya
- mis-ya
- act-3SG.M
-
- Ø
- TOP
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- ku-ada-depangas
- ku-ada-depang-as
- like-that-fool-P
- nay
- nay
- and
- ada-karayÄs.
- ada-karayÄs
- that-coward-P
‘AmÄn acts like that fool and that coward.’
-
* 
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- misya
- mis-ya
- act-3SG.M
-
- Ø
- TOP
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- ada-ku-depangas.
- ada-ku-depang-as
- that-like-fool-P
Generally, ku- fulfills the function of the preposition like in English in (30). However, if it were a preposition in Ayeri, it should trigger the locative on its dependent. In the examples above, however, the NP ku- modifies takes the patient case, like predicative NPs are otherwise wont to do. While prepositions like kong ‘inside’ in (31) are free morphemes in Ayeri, ku- is bound, which becomes apparent by introducing a parenthetical remark again:
-
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- yomÄy,
- yoma-ay.Ø
- be-1SG.TOP
- surpareng,
- surpa-reng
- seem-3SG.INAN
- kong
- kong
- inside
- sayanya.
- sayan-ya
- cave-LOC
‘I am, it seems, inside a cave.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- yomÄy
- yoma-ay.Ø
- be-1SG.TOP
- kong,
- kong
- inside
- suprareng,
- surpa-reng
- seem-3SG.INAN
- sayanya.
- sayan-ya
- cave-LOC
‘I’m inside, it seems, a cave.’
-
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- misya
- mis-ya
- act-3SG.M
-
- Ø
- TOP
- AmÄn,
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- surpareng,
- surpa-reng
- seem-3SG.INAN
- ku-depangas.
- ku-depang-as
- like-fool-P
‘AmÄn acts, it seems, like a fool.’
-
* 
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- misya
- mis-ya
- act-3SG.M
-
- Ø
- TOP
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- AmÄn
- ku,
- ku
- like
- surpareng,
- surpa-reng
- seem-3SG.INAN
- depangas.
- depang-as
- fool-P
‘AmÄn acts like a, it seems, fool.’
Examples (30ab) show that similar to the deictic prefixes, ku- precedes its target of modification and can have wide scope with coordinated NPs. As (30c) shows, narrow scope is possible as well, and in this case, again, each conjunct is to be interpreted separately instead of ku- modifying both conjuncts collectively. If combined with ada- as a deictic prefix, for instance, ku- even precedes that (30d), and changing the order of the prefixes is not possible, as is shown in (30f). As (30e) shows, ku- may also have scope over two individuating noun phrase conjuncts. Ku- is also applicable to pronouns, so (33) is possible, for example.
-
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- silvye
- silv-ye
- look-3SG.F
-
- Ø
- TOP
- Pada
- Pada
- Pada
- ku-yes.
- ku-yes
- like-3SG.F.P
‘Pada looks like her.’
-
- Sa
- sa
- PT
- silvye
- silv-ye
- look-3SG.F
- ang
- ang
- A
- Pada
- Pada
- Pada
- ku-ye.
- ku-ye
- like-3SG.F.TOP
‘Like her Pada looks.’
With proper nouns, we get the same distributional properties as with generic nouns, except that ku- appears (rather idiosyncratically) as a suffix at the right edge of an NP—or at the right edge of the first NP conjunct—if the NP is preceded by a case marker, as shown in (34). Admittedly, I hadn’t considered the behavior of ku- with names before and felt adventurous in introducing this little twist. I hope it’s viable.
-
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- lentava
- lenta-va
- sound-2.TOP
- sa
- sa
- P
- TagÄti
- TagÄti
- TagÄti
- diyan-ku.
- diyan-ku
- worthy-like
‘You sound like Mr. TagÄti.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- lentava
- lenta-va
- sound-2.TOP
- sa
- sa
- P
- TagÄti
- TagÄti
- TagÄti
- diyan-ku
- diyan-ku
- worthy-like
- nay
- nay
- and
- diranas
- diran-as
- uncle-P
- yana.
- yana
- 3SG.M.GEN
‘You sound like Mr. TagÄti and his uncle.’
-
- Sa
- sa
- PT
- lentavÄng
- lenta-vÄng
- sound-2.A
- ku-​TagÄti
- ku-​TagÄti
- like-​TagÄti
- diyan.
- diyan
- worthy
‘Like Mr. TagÄti you sound.’
With adjectives, however, there are no idiosyncrasies to this degree; ku- appears only as a prefix here, as with generic nouns:
-
-
- Surpya
- surp-ya
- seem-3SG.M
- ku-suta
- ku-suta
- like-busy
- ang
- ang
- A
- Maran.
- Maran
- Maran
‘Maran seems like he’s busy.’
-
- Surpya
- surp-ya
- seem-3SG.M
- ku-suta
- ku-suta
- like-busy
- nay
- nay
- and
- baras
- baras
- gruff
- ang
- ang
- A
- Maran.
- Maran
- Maran
‘Maran seems like he’s busy and gruff.’
As (35b) shows, ku- again can have wide scope over conjuncts. What further distinguishes ku- from a prefix here is that it doesn’t undergo crasis if the adjective begins with an /u/, hence ku-ubo /kuˈubo/ ‘like bitter’, not * kÅ«bo /ˈkuËbo/. Again, the position ku- appears in is special in that whatever modifies adjectives usually trails after them.
Another case I hadn’t considered before is that ku- should be able to subordinate infinite CPs. Since ku- leans on a whole phrase in (35), which affixes can’t do, its status as a clitic should be unmistakable in this context.
-
- Silvyeng
- silv-yeng
- look-3SG.F.A
- ku-tahayam
- ku-taha-yam
- like-have-PTCP
- misungas.
- misung-as
- secret-P
‘She looks as though having a secret.’
2. Suffixes
I hope that I could shed some light on the prefixes and particles occuring before lexical heads so far, however, Ayeri also has a number of morphemes trailing lexical heads as suffixes which do not seem quite like typical inflection. These are, for one, person suffixes on the verb, which I already tried to come to terms with in a previous blog article. In this article, I had assumed a priori that the case- and topic-marked suffixes on the verb are clitics. However, what I didn’t do is to test whether they actually fulfill formal criteria of clitics. Especially tricky in this regard is maybe that “a pronominal affix or incorporated pronominal is effectively a clitic masquerading as an affix. Therefore, if there are pronominal affixes then they should behave exactly like clitics with respect to crucial aspects of morphosyntax” (Spencer and LuÃs 2012: 144). Spencer and LuÃs (2012) then proceed to give examples from Breton and Irish where the person marking on the verb is in complementary distribution with full NPs:
-
[Breton]
-
- Bremañ
- now
- e
- PRT
- lennont
- read.PRES.3PL
- al
- the
- levrioù
- books
‘Now they are reading the books’ (145, from Borsley et al. 2007)
-
- Bremañ
- now
- e
- PRT
- lenn
- read.PRES.3SG
- ar
- the
- vugale
- children
- al
- the
- levrioù
- books
‘Now the children are reading the books’ (ibid.)
-
* 
- Bremañ
- now
- e
- PRT
- lennont
- read.PRES.3PL
- ar
- the
- vugale
- children
- al
- the
- levrioù
- books
(ibid.)
-
[Irish]
-
- Chuirfinn
- put.COND.1SG
- (*mé)
- (​I​)
- isteach
- in
- ar
- on
- an
- the
- phost
- job
- sin
- that
‘I would apply for that job’ (145, from McCloskey and Hale 1984)
-
- Chuirfeadh
- put.COND.3SG
- sibh
- you
- isteach
- in
- ar
- on
- an
- the
- phost
- job
- sin
- that
‘You would apply for that job’ (ibid.)
-
- Chuirfeadh
- put.COND.3SG
- Eoghan
- Owen
- isteach
- in
- ar
- on
- an
- the
- phost
- job
- sin
- that
‘Owen would apply for that job’ (ibid.)
What we can see in (37) is that, according to Spencer and LuÃs (2012), the verb shows no number marking, defaulting to the singular form, in non-negative clauses if the subject of the verb is overt as either a full noun or a pronoun: plural marking on the verb and a full subject can’t coincide in this case, which is why (37c) is marked ungrammatical. In (38a) we can see that there is no need for an explicit first-person pronoun, since that function is already expressed by person marking on the verb—person inflection on the verb seems to be in complementary distribution with full subject pronouns at least for some parts of the paradigm. In (38b) we have an overt 2nd-person subject pronoun, but in this case, the verb does not agree with it and instead defaults to the 3rd-person form, a clear case of which is given in (38c).
While in Ayeri, there is no defaulting to a certain person in the presence of an overt subject NP as such, there is still the effect of complementary distribution between a pronominal suffix in the absence of an overt subject NP and a functionally impoverished as well as phonologically reduced form in its presence:
-
-
- Suta
- suta
- busy
- ang
- ang
- A
- Niyas.
- Niyas
- Niyas
‘Niyas is busy.’
-
- YÄng
- yÄng
- 3SG.M.A
- suta.
- suta
- busy
‘He is busy.’
-
-
- Lampya
- lamp-ya
- walk-3SG.M
- ang
- ang
- A
- Niyas.
- Niyas
- Niyas
‘Niyas is walking.’
-
- LampyÄng.
- lamp-yÄng
- walk-3SG.M.A
‘He is walking’
-
-
* 
- LampyÄng
- lamp-yang
- walk-3SG.M.A
- ang
- ang
- A
- Niyas.
- Niyas
- Niyas
-
* 
- Lampya
- lamp-ya
- walk-3SG.M
- yÄng.
- yÄng
- 3SG.M.A
Example (39b) shows the free form of the third singular masculine agent pronoun, yÄng. This is in complementary distribution with a full NP, which in (39a) is ang Niyas. In (40a) we can see that the verb agrees with the subject NP in person, gender and number in that it exhibits the suffix -ya. If the overt subject NP is missing, the verb is marked with the same form as the free pronoun, -yÄng, which feeds the verb as a syntactic argument. That is, the person suffix itself fills the SUBJ relation of the verb’s subcategorization frame. (42) lists the constituent parts of lampyÄng and their associated grammatical features.
-
lamp- Vstem |
(↑ PRED) = ‘walk ⟨(↑ SUBJ)⟩’ |
-yÄng Vinfl |
(↑ PRED) = ‘pro’
(↑ PERS) = 3
(↑ NUM) = SG
(↑ GEND) = M
(↑ ANIM) = +
(↑ CASE) = A
|
-
PRED |
‘walk ⟨(↑ SUBJ)⟩’ |
SUBJ |
PRED |
‘pro’ |
PERS |
3 |
NUM |
SG |
GEND |
M |
ANIM |
+ |
CASE |
A |
|
Since (43) shows that functionally, the inflection takes the role of the subject relation, (41a) is ungrammatical in that the pronominal suffix -yÄng on the verb is redundant in the presence of a full NP which expresses the same features except that the subject NP’s [PRED] value is ‘Niyas’, not ‘pro’. Example (44) shows the annotations for lampya as agreeing with an overt NP. Here, the suffix does not have a [PRED] feature–it is not available for predication. The semantic features of -ya are also not defined (=), but required by constraint (=c), that is, the morpheme constrains the presence of an NP which defines these features and with which the verb thus agrees—the overt subject NP, which is the agent NP in canonical cases. By requiring that the subject’s predicator not be a pro-form in (44) it should be possible to rule out cases like in (41b), where person agreement is triggered by a pronominal NP, which is ungrammatical, since Ayeri basically supplants person agreement with a pronominal suffix in those cases. If -yÄng were a simple inflectional affix, one of the two examples in (39) should be grammatical.
-
-yaâ‚ Vinfl |
(↑ SUBJ PRED) =c ¬ ’pro’
(↑ SUBJ PERS) =c 3
(↑ SUBJ NUM) =c SG
(↑ SUBJ GEND) =c M
(↑ SUBJ ANIM) =c +
|
The behavior of the pronominal person marking on the verb is thus rather complex, and decidedly unlike inflection in that what looks like an affix on the verb is also an argument of it, like a pronoun, as displayed in (42). Another layer of complexity is added by the fact that such an incorporated pronoun is also eligible for topicalization. As we have seen above, topic marking on nouns is realized by suppressing the realization of the overt case marker, whether it is a proclitic or a suffix. The topic-marked forms of pronouns are also underspecified for case, and they happen to be the same as those of the person-agreement suffixes as exemplified by -ya in (40a). Thus, a topic-marked pronominal suffix on the verb will look exactly like ordinary agreement with a full NP, except that there is no full NP to agree with—hence the subscript numbers in (44) and (45) to distinguish between both kinds of -ya.
-
-yaâ‚‚ Vinfl |
(↑ PRED) = ‘pro’
(↑ PERS) = 3
(↑ NUM) = SG
(↑ GEND) = M
(↑ ANIM) = +
(↑ CASE) = Ø ⇒ (↑ TOP) = ↓
|
Comparing the feature list in (45) with that in (42) and (44), we see that (45) is basically the same as (42), except that either the [CASE] feature is not set, or that the suffix is underspecified for case. In absence of an NP to agree with, it follows from this definitional lack that the person marking on the verb itself is to be identified as constituting the topic, and the correspondent of the preverbal topic marker. In the following case, the preverbal topic marker defines that the topic is an animate agent:
-
ang Cl |
(↑ TOP CASE) = A
(↑ TOP ANIM) = +
|
Instances of other case-unmarked nouns can be ruled out as being also part of the topic relation on the grounds of cohesion: if the topic is defined as an agent and it can’t be assumed from context that the case-unmarked noun in question is also part of the agent NP, discard it as a candidate. Besides, every core θ-role (agent, patient, recipient) can only be assigned once, so if the role specified by the topic marker is already assigned, another NP in the same clause can’t also be assigned it. This gets more difficult with non-core roles, though I assume that oblique arguments are less likely to be topicalized.
What has led me to confusion about the status of the pronominal suffixes in the past is essentially that “a pronominal affix or incorporated pronominal is effectively a clitic masquerading as an affix” (Spencer and LuÃs 2012: 144). While the pronominal suffixes in Ayeri behave in a special way regarding syntax, they lack wide scope, which is typical of affixes (apart from the examples from Turkish quoted earlier). Unlike Breton or Irish, Ayeri’s pronominal affixes do not default to some form, and verbs cannot be unmarked either, that is, verbs always have to be inflected in some way, mostly for phonotactic reasons. Thus, in coordination, every conjunct has to be inflected for person features:
-
-
- NedrayÄng
- nedra-yÄng
- sit-3SG.M.A
- nay
- nay
- and
- layayÄng.
- laya-yÄng
- read-3SG.M.A
‘He is sitting and reading.’
-
* 
- NedrayÄng
- nedra-yÄng
- sit-3SG.M.A
- nay
- nay
- and
- laya.
- laya
- read
-
* 
- Nedra
- nedra
- sit
- nay
- nay
- and
- layayÄng.
- laya-yÄng
- read-3SG.M.A
In the case of nedra- and laya- in (47), leaving off the person marking would theoretically work, since * nedra and * laya satisfy phonotactic constraints. However, Ayeri also has a great number of verb stems which end in a consonant cluster, such as anl- ‘bring’ or tapy- ‘set’, which don’t form valid words as bare stems. What would be possible instead is that one conjunct might carry the full pronominal suffix as a “strong” form and the other one might only partially co-index the required features by using the less specific corresponding agreement marker as a “weak” form. Differential marking of this kind, though, is simply not established.
After briefly delving into the realm of syntax, let’s return to morphology for the second group of suffixes which could use some clarification. While Ayeri has quantifiers which are independent words, there are also a number of very common ‘little’ quantifiers and degree adverbs which are customarily spelled as suffixes, for instance, -ikan ‘much, many; very’, -kay ‘few; a little’, -nama ‘almost’, -nyama ‘even’. All of these are adverbial in meaning and while they are comparatively light in their semantics compared to regular content words, I can’t say that they strike me as functional morphemes in particular. In the course of writing this article, an article which has come up in my searches a number of times is Bittner (1995) on quantification in West Greenlandic. According to her terminology, -ikan in Ayeri would be a D-quantifier, which “forms a constituent with, a projection of N” (Bittner 1995: 59), in contrast to A-quantifiers, which form “a constituent with some projection of V” (59). That is, A-quantifiers are adverbs like almost (-nama in Ayeri), mostly, or never, while D-quantifiers are words like most, some, or every. Ayeri makes no distinction between A- and D-quantifiers with regards to their being treated as suffixes, so one can find suffixed quantifiers in both groups. While my main interest here is in the morphosyntax of these quantifiers, Bittner’s is in their semantics, though the article gives evidence notwithstanding of a language in which suffixed quantifiers are attested, for example:
-
[West Greenlandic]
-
- qaatuur-tuaanna-ngajap-p-a-a
- break-always-almost-IND-TR-3SGâ‚.3SGâ‚‚
‘he almost always breaks it’ (adapted from Bittner 1995: 60)
-
- qaqutigu-rujussuaq
- rarely-very
‘very rarely’ (63)
-
-
- ang
- ang
- AT
- adruya
- adru-ya.Ø
- break-3SG.M.TOP
- tadayen-ngas
- tadayen-ngas
- always-almost
- adaley
- ada-ley
- that-P.INAN
‘he almost always breaks it’
-
‘very rarely’
As we can see in (48a), West Greenlandic incorporates the quantifier suffixes into the verb, while Ayeri—not a polysynthetic language—proceeds more freely in (49a) in that tadayen ‘always, every time’ is an adverb and as such a free morpheme which is, however, in turn modified by a suffixed quantifier. Since orthography may be treacherous, let’s first try to establish whether -ngas and -ikan and their like are free morphemes or not. As discussed initially regarding the preverbal particles, it is possible to reorder free morphemes, while clitics, as bound morphemes, can’t move around. Adverbs and adjectives are, if they optionally add additional information to a lexical head, adjuncts, and according to Carnie (2013) it is possible for adjuncts to switch places within the same syntactic domain. Adjuncts can also be coordinated with other adjuncts in the same syntactic domain. Furthermore, it is possible to replace X’ nodes with pro-forms, like one in English.
-
-
- kipisÄnye-ikan
- kipisÄn-ye-ikan
- painting-PL-many
- bino
- bino
- colorful
- kÄryo
- kÄryo
- big
‘many big colorful paintings’
-
kipisÄnye-ikan kÄryo bino
‘many big colorful paintings’
-
! kipisÄnye bino-ikan kÄryo
‘very colorful big paintings’
-
! kipisÄnye bino kÄryo-ikan
‘very big colorful paintings’
-
-
- kipisÄnye-ikan
- kipisÄn-ye-ikan
- painting-PL-many
- bino
- bino
- colorful
- nay
- nay
- and
- kÄryo
- kÄryo
- big
‘many big and colorful paintings’
-
* kipisÄnye-ikan nay bino kÄryo
‘many and colorful big paintings’
-
! kipisÄnye bino-ikan nay kÄryo
‘big and very colorful paintings’
As (50cd) shows, moving -ikan ‘many, much, very’ into different positions results not necessarily in ungrammatical expressions, but in ones with meanings different from what was intended, since -ikan‘s scope changes from the noun to the adjective it is appended to. On the other hand, comparing (50a) and (b), it is possible for kÄryo ‘big’ and bino ‘colorful’ to switch places with no adversary effects. Example (51b) demonstrates that placing a coordinating conjunction between -ikan and bino ‘colorful’ doesn’t work. The coordination in (51c), on the other hand, is not a problem—not because it is possible to coordinate -ikan and kÄryo, but because bino-ikan ‘very colorful’ is considered one syntactic unit which is coordinated with kÄryo. Thus, in (50b), we have actually been trying to coordinate kipisÄnye-ikan ‘many paintings’ with bino ‘colorful’, which does not work, since it is not possible to coordinate a lexical head with an adjunct supposed to modify it, since they are of different syntactic categories. In this regard it is worth mentioning that Ayeri’s quantifier suffixes are rather not complements either, since they are not required in order to satisfy their head’s argument structure.
One might argue that in (50) and (51) we tried to compare apples to oranges in that -ikan and bino are of different categories, since -ikan and bino don’t appear to operate on the same levels. So instead, let’s look at possibilities of word order change and coordination between different quantifiers to ensure that we actually stay on the same level. With this there is the problem, however, that it seems strange to modify the same lexical head with multiple different quantifiers, so this test does not really seem feasible to produce grammatical results. Also, with regards to coordination of quantifiers, it is maybe more natural to oppose them with soyang ‘or’ than to coordinate them; the grammatical structure of two categorially identical elements connected by a grammatical conjunction (even if the meaning is disjunctive) remains the same in either case.
-
-
* 
- keynam-ikan-kay
- keynam-ikan-kay
- people-many-few
‘few many people’
-
? 
- keynam-ikan
- keynam-ikan
- people-many
- soyang
- soyang
- or
- -kay
- -kay
- few
‘few or many people’
In example (52a) we see that it is indeed not possible to combine multiple quantifiers to jointly modify a head in the way it is possible for multiple adjectives to modify the same head as in (50a), for instance. The example of quantifier disjunction in (52b) is also odd unless we permit a reading where keynam ‘people’ has been suppressed in the second disjunct to avoid repetition, although in the corresponding case of (53b) below, da-kay would be preferable.
-
-
? keynam[-ikan soyang kay]
‘[few or many] people’
-
[keynami-ikan] soyang [_i-kay]
‘[few _i] or [many peoplei]’
Both tests, moving -ikan into other positions and coordination, have failed so far, and we have evidence that -ikan forms a syntactic unit with its head, which points to it being a bound morpheme similar to an affix in spite of its adverb-like meaning. As with free words, it is also possible to replace a quantifier’s head with a pro-form, as mentioned above in the comment on (53b), and shown in more detail in (54). With quantifier suffixes there seems to be an overlap between word-like and affix-like properties, which is typical of clitics.
-
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- vacyan
- vac-yan
- like-3SG.M
- keynam-ikan
- keynam-Ø-ikan
- people-TOP-many
- seygoley.
- seygo-ley.
- apple-P.INAN
‘Many people like apples.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- vacyan
- vac-yan
- like-3SG.M
- danya-ikan
- danya-Ø-ikan
- such.one-TOP-many
- seygoley.
- seygo-ley.
- apple-P.INAN
‘Many of them like apples.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- vacyan
- vac-yan
- like-3SG.M
- da-ikan
- da-ikan-Ø
- one-many-TOP
- seygoley.
- seygo-ley.
- apple-P.INAN
‘Many (of them) like apples.’
Somewhat untypical of affixes, it seems to be possible to modify suffixed quantifier with adverbs like ekeng ‘too’ and kagan ‘far too’, as (55) shows. This suggests that at least in this context, -ikan may actually be the lexical head of an adverbial phrase, which is at odds with its status as a bound morpheme.
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- vacyan
- vac-yan
- like-3SG.M
- keynam-ikan
- keynam-Ø-ikan
- people-TOP-many
- kagan
- kagan
- far.too
- disuley.
- disu-ley.
- disu-P.INAN
‘Far too many people like bananas.’
I previously tried to insert parenthetical word material in between morphemes, and this test may be especially interesting in face of (55), since here it is not entirely clear whether keynam-ikan kagan ‘too many people’ forms a single unit. Since signs point to the status of quantifier suffixes as clitics, chances are good that it does, in fact, constitute a clitic cluster similar to the preverbal one. Example (56), therefore, lists examples which try to split up the expression at every relevant point. According to this test, it looks indeed as though keynam-ikan kagan forms a syntactic unit, in that -ikan kagan ‘too many’ cannot be split up internally and also cannot be divided from -ikan‘s head, keynam ‘people’.
-
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- vacyan,
- vac-yan
- like-3SG.M
- ​​narayang​​,
- nara-yang
- say-1SG.A
- keynam-ikan
- keynam-Ø-ikan
- people-TOP-many
- kagan
- kagan
- far.too
- disuley.
- disu-ley
- disu-P.INAN
‘Far too many people, I say, like bananas.’
- * Ang vacyan keynam, narayang, ikan kagan disuley.
- * Ang vacyan keynam-ikan, narayang, kagan disuley.
- Ang vacyan keynam-ikan kagan, narayang, disuley.
Another interesting distributional property of suffixed quantifiers in Ayeri is that in spite of their being suffixed, to verbs for instance, they can form arguments of the verb, similar to pronominal suffixes. Thus, with verbs like kond- ‘eat’, -ma ‘enough’ appears suffixed to the verb instead of as a predicative adverb. Incidentally, the examples in (56) also show that a quantifier attaches after pronominal suffixes, which we have already established as being clitics. An inflectional affix would not normally appear in post-clitic position, which is further evidence to the hypothesis that quantifier suffixes in Ayeri are clitics.
-
-
- Kondanang-ma.
- kond-nang-ma
- eat-1PL.A-enough
‘We ate enough.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- tangay-ikan
- tang-ay.Ø-ikan
- hear-1SG.TOP-much
- vana.
- vana
- 2.GEN
‘I’ve heard much about you.’
Since Ayeri possesses a zero copula, equative phrases which treat quantifier suffixes as predicative adverbs pose a difficulty in that quantifier suffixes cannot stand alone like predicatives normally would. Thus, in a similar fashion to -ma‘s behavior in (57a), the predicative -ma in (58b) cliticizes to the only available word: the subject, adareng ‘that’.
-
-
- Adareng
- ada-reng
- that-A.INAN
- edaya.
- edaya
- here
‘It is here.’
-
- Adareng-ma.
- ada-reng-ma
- that-A.INAN-enough
‘That/It is enough.’
If quantifier suffixes are clitics, they should also have wide scope over conjuncts. Here as well, quantifier suffixes behave typically of clitics, though, in that they can have scope over a conjunct as a whole, although not totally unambiguously so.
-
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- tahisayan
- tahisa-yan.Ø
- own-3PL.M.TOP
- koyÄs
- koya-as
- book-P
- nay
- nay
- and
- kihasley-ikan.
- kihas-ley-ikan
- map-P.INAN-many
‘They own many books and maps.’
-
- Yeng
- yeng
- 3SG.F.A
- alingo
- alingo
- clever
- nay
- nay
- and
- para-ven.
- para-ven
- quick-pretty
‘She’s pretty clever and quick.’
Thus, in (59a), while koyÄs nay kihasley-ikan is translated as ‘many books and maps’ (nouns do not mark plural if modified by a quantifier which indicates plurality), another possible reading is ‘a book and many maps’. Ways to force the latter reading explicitly are, for one, to use koyÄs men ‘one/a single book’, or alternatively, to reduplicate the coordinator nay ‘and’ to naynay ‘and also’. Context should be sufficient to indicate the correct reading of (59a) under normal circustances, however. The same applies to (59b), where the non-distributive reading can be made explicit by using naynay instead of simple nay. In both (59a) and (b), if the first conjunct is modified by an adjective, the distribution of the quantifier over both conjuncts is also blocked. Thus, in (60a), there is ‘a big book and many maps’, and in (60b) ‘she’ is ‘surprisingly clever and pretty quick’.
-
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- tahisayan
- tahisa-yan.Ø
- own-3PL.M.TOP
- koyÄs
- koya-as
- book-P
- kÄryo
- kÄryo
- big
- nay
- nay
- and
- kihasley-ikan.
- kihas-ley-ikan
- map-P.INAN-many
‘They own a big book and many maps.’
Not: ‘They own many big books and maps.’
-
- Yeng
- yeng
- 3SG.F.A
- alingo
- alingo
- clever
- patu
- patu
- surprisingly
- nay
- nay
- and
- para-ven.
- para-ven
- quick-pretty
‘She’s surprisingly clever and pretty quick.’
Not: ‘She is surprisingly pretty clever and quick.’
The false interpretations in (60) can be correctly achieved by ordinarily placing the adjective after the compounds so that the adjective itself has scope over both conjuncts. This is demonstrated in (61) and (62). Again, an unambiguous and individuating interpretation can be achieved by placing the quantifier suffix on each conjunct.
-
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- tahisayan
- tahisa-yan.Ø
- own-3PL.M.TOP
- koyajas
- koya-ye-as
- book-PL-P
- nay
- nay
- and
- kihasyeley
- kihas-ye-ley
- map-PL-P.INAN
- kÄryo.
- kÄryo
- big
‘They own big books and maps.’
-
- Ang
- ang
- AT
- tahisayan
- tahisa-yan.Ø
- own-3PL.M.TOP
- koyÄs
- koya-as
- book-PL-P
- nay
- nay
- and
- kihasley-ikan
- kihas-ley-ikan
- map-P.INAN-many
- kÄryo.
- kÄryo
- big
‘They own many big books and maps.’
-
-
- Yeng
- yeng
- 3SG.F.A
- alingo
- alingo
- clever
- nay
- nay
- and
- para
- para
- quick
- patu.
- patu
- surprisingly
‘She’s surprisingly clever and quick.’
-
- Yeng
- yeng
- 3SG.F.A
- alingo
- alingo
- clever
- nay
- nay
- and
- para-ven
- para-ven
- quick-pretty
- patu.
- patu
- surprisingly
‘She’s surprisingly pretty clever and quick.’
3. Conclusive remarks
I have applied various tests, mostly of morphosyntactic nature, to particles occurring in front of verbs, nouns, and adjectives, as well as to suffixes indicating person features on verbs, and to quantifier suffixes on a variety of parts of speech in order test whether these particles, prefixes, and suffixes behave like clitics in spite of appearing like function words, adverbs, prefixes, or suffixes. By testing morphosyntactic properties of the various morphemes evidence was presented to argue that (1) the preverbal particles form a clitic cluster together with the verb; (2) da- and sitang- on verbs are likely clitics; (3) da- on nouns, adjectives and possessive pronouns are clitics; (4) the preposed case markers of names are likely clitics; (5) deictic prefixes on the noun are likely clitics; (6) pronominal suffixes on verbs are clitics for their special syntax and in spite of the suffixes’ narrow scope, which is at least in part due to phonotactic requirements; and (7), suffixed quantifiers are clitics in spite of their adverbial meaning.
- Bittner, Maria. “Quantification in Eskimo: A Challenge for Compositional Semantics.” Quantification in Natural Languages. Ed. by Emmon Bach et al. Dordrecht: Springer, 1995. 59–80. Print. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy 54. DOI: 10.1007/978-94-017-2817-1_4.
- Borsley, Robert D., Maggie Tallerman, and David Willis. The Syntax of Welsh. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2007. Print.
- Bresnan, Joan et al. Lexical-Functional Syntax. 2nd ed. Chichester: Wiley Blackwell, 2016. Print. Blackwell Textbooks in Linguistics 16.
- Butt, Miriam and Tracy Holloway King. “Lexical-Functional Grammar.” Syntax—Theory and Analysis: An International Handbook. Vol. 2. Ed. by Tibor Kiss and Artemis Alexiadou. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton, 2015. 839–74. Handbücher zur Sprach- und Kommunikationswissenschaft 42. Web. 10 Apr. 2015. DOI: 10.1515/9783110363708-002.
- Carnie, Andrew. Syntax: A Generative Introduction. 3rd ed. Chichester: Wiley Blackwell, 2013. Print. Introducing Linguistics 4.
- Halpern, Aaron. “Clitics.” The Handbook of Morphology. Ed. by Andrew Spencer and Arnold M. Zwicky. Oxford: Blackwell, 1998. 101–22. Print.
- Hammarström, Harald et al. “Language: Kwak’wala.” Glottolog. Version 3.0. Max Planck Institute for the Science of Human History, n.d. Web. 10 Apr. 2017. ‹http://glottolog.org/resource/languoid/id/kwak1269›.
- Klavans, Judith L. “The Independence of Syntax and Phonology in Cliticization.” Language 61.1 (1985): 95–120. Web. 20 Jul. 2016. ‹http://www.jstor.org/stable/413422›.
- Levine, Robert D. “On the Lexical Origin of the Kwakwala passive.” International Journal of Linguistics 46.4 (1980): 240–59. Web. 10 Apr. 2017. ‹http://www.jstor.org/stable/1264707›.
- McCloskey, James and Ken Hale. “On the Syntax of Person-Number Inflection in Modern Irish.” Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 1.4 (1984). 487–534. Print. DOI: 10.1007/BF00417057.
- [Smedt,] Koenraad [de]. “Feature Table.” ParGram/ParSem: An International Collaboration on LFG-Based Grammar and Semantics Development. 2017. U of Bergen, 1 Feb. 2011. Web. 8 Apr. 2017. ‹https://pargram.b.uib.no›.
- Spencer, Andrew and Ana R. LuÃs. Clitics: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2012. Print. Cambridge Textbooks in Linguistics.
- Wälchli, Bernhard. Co-compounds and Natural Coordination. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2005. Print.
- Zwicky, Arnold M. On Clitics. Bloomington: Indiana U Linguistics Club, 1977. Web. 22 Jul. 2016. ‹https://web.stanford.edu/~zwicky/on_clitics.pdf›.
- ——— and Geoffrey K. Pullum. “Cliticization vs. Inflection: English N’T.” Language 59.3 (1983): 502–13. Web. 21 Jul. 2016. ‹http://www.jstor.org/stable/413900›.